Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 18

Two Kinds of Skeptical Argument

Author(s): Stewart Cohen


Source: Philosophy and Phenomenological Research , Mar., 1998, Vol. 58, No. 1 (Mar.,
1998), pp. 143-159
Published by: International Phenomenological Society

Stable URL: https://www.jstor.org/stable/2653634

JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
https://about.jstor.org/terms

is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Philosophy and
Phenomenological Research

This content downloaded from


67.249.89.178 on Wed, 08 Jun 2022 00:38:03 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Philosophy and Phenomenological Research
Vol. LVIII, No. 1, March 1998

Two Kinds of Skeptical Argument

STEWART COHEN

Arizona State University

This paper compares two kinds of epistemic principles-an underdetermination princi-


ple and a deductive closure principle. It argues that each principle provides the basis for
an independently motivated skeptical argument. It examines the logical relations
between the premises of the two kinds of skeptical argument and concludes that the
deductive closure argument cannot be refuted without refuting the underdetermination
argument. The underdetermination argument, however, can be refuted without refuting
the deductive closure argument. In this respect, the deductive closure argument is the
stronger of the two.

Skepticism can be viewed as a problem that derives from the plausibility of


certain epistemic deductive closure principles. But skepticism can also seen as
a problem that stems from the plausibility of certain epistemic underdetermi-
nation principles. What is the relative importance of these two kinds of prin-
ciples for formulating skeptical arguments?
According to one view, skeptical arguments must appeal to a deductive
closure principle and do not require any appeal to an underdetermination prin-
ciple.1 At the other extreme, some have held that skeptical arguments require
an appeal to an underdetermination principle and that any appeal to a deduc-
tive closure principle is superfluous.2
I propose to defend a more moderate view, viz., that each principle pro-
vides the basis for an independently motivated skeptical argument. Because of
this, neither principle is required to make the case for skepticism, nor is
either principle superfluous. I will also argue that the deductive closure argu-
ment is, by one measure, the stronger argument.

I See Robert Nozick, Philosophical Explanations (Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard


University Press, 1981), chapter 3, and Fred Dretske, "Epistemic Operators", Journal of
Philosophy (December 1970).
2 See Anthony Brueckner, "The Structure of the Skeptical Argument", Philosophy and
Phenomenological Research (December 1994) and Omit D. Yeltsin, "Skeptical Argu-
ments from Underdetermination", 68 Philosophical Studies (1992), pp. 106-22

TWO KINDS OF SKEPTICAL ARGUMENTS 143

This content downloaded from


67.249.89.178 on Wed, 08 Jun 2022 00:38:03 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
I

We can begin by considering a recent argument put forth by Anthony


Brueckner.3 Brueckner argues that once we get clear on the structure of the
"canonical Cartesian skeptical argument", we will see that the appeal to
deductive closure principles is superfluous. He begins by considering skepti-
cal argument A-a first statement of the canonical argument. Let P be some
arbitrary proposition about the external world, such as I see a table, and let
SK be a proposition about a skeptical hypothesis incompatible with P, such
as I am a brain-in-a-vat with sense experience that is qualitatively indistin-
guishable from my actual experience:

(1A) If I know P, then I know not-SK.

(2A) I do not know not-SK

(3A) I do not know P

In defense of (1A), the skeptic appeals to a deductive closure principle.


Brueckner suggests that the principle be formulated in this way:

(CK) For all S, A, if S knows 0 and S knows that 0 entails A,


then S knows A.

Assuming I know that P entails not-SK, we can derive (1A) from (CK).
According to Brueckner, argument A ultimately relies on an underdetermi-
nation principle, as well. In defense of (2A), the skeptic appeals to

(UP) For all S, 0, W, if S's evidence does not favor 0 over some
incompatible hypothesis W, then S's evidence does not justify
o.4

In particular the skeptic appeals to this instance of (UP):

(*) If my evidence does not favor not-SK over SK, my evidence does
not justify not-SK.

Brueckner, ibid. The relation between a closure principle and an underdetermination


principle was discussed by Jonathan Vogel, Cartesian Skepticism and Epistemic Princi-
ples (Doctoral dissertation, Yale University, 1986). Vogel argued that certain formula-
tions of the principles are interderivable, as Brueckner does. In more recent work, Vogel
explores a weaker version of an underdetermination principle, and arrives at a position
that is somewhat similar to the one I defend here (see his "Skepticism and Knowledge of
the External World, in preparation).
In Brueckner's statement of the principle, the consequent of the conditional is "S lacks
justification for believing that O." I state it the way I do for ease of exposition. The differ-
ence does not matter to the argument.
In my statement, "S's evidence does not justify 4" means that S's evidence does not
provide justification for believing 4.

144 STEWART COHEN

This content downloaded from


67.249.89.178 on Wed, 08 Jun 2022 00:38:03 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
This requires, of course, the further claim

(**) My evidence does not favor not-SK over SK.

To articulate further the structure of the skeptical argument, Brueckner


notes that there is a justification analog for (CK):

(CJ) For all S, 0, A, if S's evidence justifies 0, and 0 entails A, then


S's evidence justifies W. I

This enables us to formulate Brueckner's skeptical argument B:

(1B) If my evidence justifies P, then my evidence justifies not-SK.


[from (CJ)]

(2B) If my evidence does not favor not-SK over SK, then my evidence
does not justify not-SK. [from (UP)]

(3B) My evidence does not favor not-SK over SK. [premise]

(4B) My evidence does not justify not-SK. [from 2B, 3B]

(5B) My evidence does not justify P. [from 1B, 4B]

(6B) I do not know P. [from 5B]

As it stands, the skeptical argument appeals to two epistemic principles-


(CJ) and (UP). But Brueckner observes "that the skeptical reasoning we are
trying to capture can be simplified in such a way that it only makes appeal to
one epistemic principle. We need not appeal to the closure principle."6 Here
is argument C-his final version of the skeptical argument:

(iC) If my evidence does not favor P over SK, then my evidence does
not justify P. [from UP]

Brueckner mentions two principles:

(CIJ) For all S, 4, A, if S has justification for believing that 4 and S knows that 4
entails A, then S has justification for believing that A.

(CIV) For all S, 4, A, if S has justification for believing that 4, and 4 entails A, that
S has justification for believing A.

(CIJ) is stronger though Brueckner argues that it is as plausible as (CIJ) since S can have
justification for believing 4 without actually believing it. Brueckner mentions a worry
about (CIJ) concerning necessary truths and I think there are additional worries as well.
In the end, I think they can be handled with minor modifications. (Brueckner suggest
restricting (CIJ') to contingent W's.) None of these worries affect the substantive issue
that I will discuss so I will stick to Brueckner's (CIJ') for ease of exposition. I will simply
call it "(CJ)" however.
One final point: As I did in the case of (UP), I have, in stating (CJ) substituted "S's
evidence justifies P" for "S has justification for believing P"
Brueckner, op. cit., p. 833.

TWO KINDS OF SKEPTICAL ARGUMENTS 145

This content downloaded from


67.249.89.178 on Wed, 08 Jun 2022 00:38:03 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
(2C) My evidence does not favor P over SK. [premise]

(3C) My evidence does not justify P. [from 1C, 2C]

(4C) I do not know P. [from 3C]

So, if Brueckner is correct about the structure of the skeptical argument,


then a deductive closure principle like (CJ) turns out to be superfluous to the
skeptical argument.

II

The thrust of Brueckner's remarks is that the Cartesian skeptical problem,


although traditionally conceived as a problem stemming from deductive clo-
sure, is in fact a problem stemming from underdetermination. Let us examine
more closely how he arrives at this conclusion.
His final reconstruction of what he calls "the canonical Cartesian skeptical
argument" is given in argument C. We were led to argument C in trying to
find support for (2A) in the original version of the skeptical argument. That
argument appeals to the deductive closure principle (CK). Given (CJ), how-
ever, we can display more of the structure of the deductive closure argument:

(iD) If my evidence justifies P, then my evidence justifies not-SK.


[from CJ]

(2D) My evidence does not justify not-SK. [premise]

(3D) My evidence does not justify P. [from 1E, 2D]

(4D) I do not know P. [from 3E]

As we can see from argument B, Brueckner holds that, in the end, we must
appeal to (3B) (My evidence does not favor SK over not-SK) in defense of the
premise (2D) (My evidence does not justify not-SK). But (3B) works in con-
junction with (UP). And we can see from argument C that once we appeal to
(UP) we can eliminate any appeal to (CJ).
But Brueckner has given no argument that we must appeal to (3B) in sup-
port of (2D). And I can see no reason to suppose that we must. (2D) says that
my evidence does not justify not-SK. Suppose we conceive of my evidence as
being represented by the proposition E.7 Now one thing that is particularly
salient about the skeptical hypothesis SK is that if SK were true, it would
explain the truth of E. But having noted this, it becomes extremely puzzling,
to say the least, how that very evidence could justify not-SK. Thus, it
becomes very hard to resist accepting (2D).8

7 This is a harmless simplifying assumption. We could express the point without it though it
would be more cumbersome.
8 We can think of this reasoning as appealing to the principle:

146 STEWART COHEN

This content downloaded from


67.249.89.178 on Wed, 08 Jun 2022 00:38:03 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
My claim is not that this reasoning will move everyone to skeptical
doubt. But I do think it represents a very natural motivation for premise (2D).
As an example, consider Robert Nozick's discussion of the origins of skepti-
cal doubt. After introducing the possibility that some skeptical hypothesis
like SK is true, he writes:

If one of these other things was happening, your experience would be exactly the same as it
now is. So how can you know none of them is happening?9

The important thing about this reasoning is that it does not rely on the
underdetermination premise (3B). In fact, it looks as if one who reasons in
this way could reject (3B) altogether. Suppose I think E favors (to some
degree) P over SK, and so favors not-SK over SK. I need not hold that E
favors P, and not-SK, enough to justify either P or not-SK. But then I see no
reason why one who believes E favors not-SK over SK, i.e., one who rejects
(3B), cannot reason that because the truth of SK would explain the truth of E,
E cannot justify not-SK.10
This shows that we can view skeptical argument D as a straight deductive
closure argument-we need not view it as appealing to the underdetermina-
tion principle (UP). So there is no reason to think that (UP) is central to the

(Z) For all S, 4, if the truth of 4 would explain S's evidence, then S's evidence does
not justify not-?
The order of justification is not clear here. It may be that the general principle (Z) has no
more intuitive plausibility than the particular claim (2D). One possibility (suggested by an
anonymous referee) is that the particular claim and the general principle provide mutual
support through a process of reflective equilibrium.
I do not think, however, that the initial plausibility of (2D) depends on our being able
to precisely articulate a general principle from which it can be derived. One way to think
of this is that the plausibility of (2D) stems from an intuition about the concept of eviden-
tial support or justification. The intuition persists even if we are unable to come up with a
general account that explains the intuition. On this view, the plausibility of (2D) is very
much like the plausibility of the denial of the (sub)conclusion of the skeptical argument-
My evidence does justify P. The claim that my evidence does justify P has enormous
intuitive plausibility. And its initial plausibility does not depend on our being able to articu-
late a general principle of justification from which it follows. This is what explains our
resistance to skeptical arguments. For this reason, the skeptical problem is best viewed as
a paradox, a set of incompatible propositions, each of which has considerable intuitive
plausibility.
Also (an anonymous referee noted that) the case where P is a contradiction looks
worrisome for principle (Z), given standard semantics for subjunctive conditionals.
Because of this we can restrict the principle to non-contradictions.
9 Op. cit., p.167. For further examples of philosophers who see the skeptical problem as
being motivated in roughly this way, see John Pollock, Contemporary Theories of Knowl-
edge (Rowan and Littlefield, 1986), p. 3, and Barry Stroud, The Significance of Philosoph-
ical Skepticism (Oxford, 1984) pp. 20-21.
10 Brueckner seemingly makes this same point though his statement of it is puzzling. He
says, "...S's evidence might favor one of two incompatible hypotheses without being
strong enough to justify a belief of either". See footnote 7, Ibid. Presumably he means to
say "...to justify a belief in the favored hypothesis or the denial of the unfavored hypoth-
esis."

TWO KINDS OF SKEPTICAL ARGUMENTS 147

This content downloaded from


67.249.89.178 on Wed, 08 Jun 2022 00:38:03 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
"canonical skeptical argument" while (CJ) is superfluous. In fact we have two
skeptical arguments, argument C based on (UP) and argument D based on
(CJ).
My point is not that we must, in the end, endorse this reasoning in sup-
port of (2D) (or 2D itself). Neither must we accept the underdetermination
based reasoning to which Brueckner appeals. (Brueckner himself raises what
he takes to be a serious objection to the underdetermination based reason-
ing.") Most philosophers presuppose that there has to be something wrong
with any argument for skepticism. Nonetheless, for many, the premises of
these arguments have enough plausibility to make skepticism a philosophical
problem worth taking seriously. My point is only that insofar as there is a
philosophical problem of skepticism, deductive closure and underdetermina-
tion appear to be distinct sources.

III

The underdetermination principle (UP) and the deductive closure principle


(CJ) each leads to skeptical problems via a different route. (UP) proceeds
through (2C) (My evidence does not favor P over SK) while (CJ) proceeds
through (2D) (My evidence does not favor not-SK). This makes it look as if
the issue of whether one principle generates skeptical problems is logically
independent of the issue of whether the other principle generates skeptical
problems. But this turns out not to be true.

Brueckner, op. cit. p. 835. Brueckner says the motivation for (2C) (my evidence does not
favor P over SK) is that E (my evidence) would be true, regardless of whether P or SK is
true. This is similar to what I state as the motivation for (2D). I appeal to the fact that if
SK were true, it would explain the truth of E. This is because the mere fact that E would
be true if SK were true does not seem to be enough. Let SK be the bare hypothesis (not-P
& E). The mere fact that if SK were true, E would be true, does not seem to count against
saying that E justifies not-SK. We need some skeptical hypothesis that would explain the
truth of E. That is the reason for specifying the hypothesis that I am a brain-in-a-vat...
For this reason, the motivation for (2C) is better conceived as the fact that the truth of
E would be explained, regardless of whether P or SK is true.
Brueckner argues that this reasoning in support of (2C) "ultimately derives from" the
controversial view that the evidence required to justify P must entail P. (p. 835) I find
Brueckner's argument for this conclusion somewhat unclear. I do think this much is true.
The reasoning in support of (2C) may, in conjunction with (UP), provide an argument for
this controversial "entailment" view. For E's not entailing P would seem to be all that is
needed for the skeptic to argue that there is some Q incompatible with P, such that E does
not favor P over Q. (Similar consideration apply to the motivation I have suggested for
(2D.)
Is this a problem for the reasoning in support of (2C)? Arguably, a large part of what
makes the entailment view controversial is that it leads to skepticism. It is not that the
view has no intuitive appeal. (Recall that we are concerned here with justification to the
degree necessary for knowledge.) It is just that most philosophers have opted for reject-
ing this view over accepting skepticism. Insofar as the reasoning for (2C) in conjunction
with (UP) leads to the entailment view, we have an additional argument for the entail-
ment view.

148 STEWART COHEN

This content downloaded from


67.249.89.178 on Wed, 08 Jun 2022 00:38:03 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
(UP) and (CJ) will have skeptical significance only for those cases where
S's evidence does not justify not-?. For if S's evidence does justify not-?, it
is uncontroversially true, independently of either (UP) or (CJ), that S fails to
know 0.12
So let's suppose my evidence does not justify not-P. We can then show
that, although (2D) can be true without (2C) being true, (2C) cannot be true
without (2D) being true.
Suppose E (my evidence) favors P over SK. Still, as we just noted in sec-
tion II, E may not favor P enough to justify either P or not-SK. If, for
example, Pr(P/E)=.5 while Pr(SK/E)=.4, then E favors P over SK, while E
fails to justify not-SK. But then (2D) (My evidence does not justify not-SK)
is true, while (2C) (My evidence does not favor P over SK) is false.13
Now suppose E does justify not-SK (the denial of 2D). Then E must favor
P over SK (the denial of 2C). Where E justifies not-SK, E fails to favor P
over SK only if E justifies not-P. But we are assuming E does not justify
not-P. Thus the denial of (2D) entails the denial of (2C) and so (relative to
our assumption) (2C) entails (2D).14
Here is the derivation of (2D) from (2C):

(1) E does not favor P over SK. [(2C)]

(2) E justifies not-SK. [denial of (2D), assume for reductio]

(3) E does not justify not-P. [premise]

(4) E justifies not-P. [from 1, 2]

So although (relative to our assumption) (2D) can be true without (2C)


being true, (2C) cannot be true without (2D) being true. So, in principle, the
deductive closure principle (CJ) can have skeptical consequences without the
underdetermination principle (UP) having any such consequences. But if the

12 I am assuming that S's evidence cannot justify both 4 and not-?.


13 I mean to be making a logical point here-that where 4 and v are incompatible proposi-
tions, my evidence could favor 4 over A, without favoring 4 enough to justify 4 or not-v.
Now one might think that in the case of P and not-SK, the evidence could not favor P
over not-SK or that there could be no reason for thinking that the evidence favors P over
SK that was not also a reason for thinking the evidence justifies not-SK. But it would take
an argument to show this. In section V, I discuss one kind of antiskeptical strategy which
if correct, would make defensible the view that (2D) is true but (2C) is false.
14 If (2C) and (2D) are true, they are necessarily true. So, if they are true, each will entail
the other. When I say (2C) entails (2D), but not conversely, I mean that anyone who
accepts (2C) is committed to accepting (2D), but not conversely.
Moreover, as is clear from the derivation in the text that follows, one is so committed
only if one accepts this principle:

For all S, 4, A, if S's evidence does not favor 4 over v and S's evidence justifies not-
y, then S's evidence justifies not-?.

But that principle looks to be a necessary truth.

TWO KINDS OF SKEPTICAL ARGUMENTS 149

This content downloaded from


67.249.89.178 on Wed, 08 Jun 2022 00:38:03 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
underdetermination principle (UP) has skeptical consequences, then so does
the deductive closure principle (CJ).

IV

Given that (UP) has skeptical consequences only if (CJ) does one might think
that a skeptic who accepts (CJ) has little to gain by appealing to (UP). We
will take up this issue in section VI. For now we can see that regardless of
whether there is anything to be gained by it, one who accepts (CJ) is com-
mitted to accepting (UP). For it is a consequence of my argument in section
III, that (CJ) entails (UP).
To see how, it will be useful to refer to an observation of Brueckner's. He
notes that (UP) is equivalent to

(UP') For all S, 0, A, if S's evidence justifies 0, and 0 and v are


incompatible, then S's evidence favors 0 over A.

and that (CJ) is equivalent to

(CY) For all S, 0, W, if S's evidence justifies 0, and 0 and v are


incompatible, then S's evidence justifies not-W.

In section III, I argued that (2C) (My evidence does not favor P over SK)
entails (2D) (My evidence does not justify not-SK). If so, the denial of the
consequent of the conditional embedded in (UP') entails the denial of the con-
sequent of the conditional embedded in (CY). Since the antecedents of the
conditionals embedded in the two principles are identical, it follows that (CY)
entails (UP'). Thus (CJ) entails (UP).'"
We can show this more straightforwardly by deriving the consequent of
the conditional embedded in (UP') from the conditional embedded in (CY) and
the antecedent of conditional embedded in (UP,):16

(1) If S's evidence justifies 0, and 0 and v are incompatible, then


S's evidence justifies not-W. [(CJ')]

(2) S's evidence justifies 0, and 0 and v are incompatible.


[antecedent of (UP')]

(3) S's evidence justifies not-W. [from 1, 2]

(4) S's evidence justifies 0 and S's evidence justifies not-iv. [from 2,
3]

15 As we noted, (2C) entails (2D) only given the restriction that S's evidence does not justify
not-?. But this restriction is entailed by the antecedent of the conditionals. So my conclu-
sion that (CJ) entails (UP) is unaffected.
16 Here I follow Brueckner's reasoning in ft. 7, op. cit., p. 7.

150 STEWART COHEN

This content downloaded from


67.249.89.178 on Wed, 08 Jun 2022 00:38:03 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
(5) S's evidence favors 0 over iy. [from 4]17

Brueckner makes the stronger claim that (CJ) and (UP) are equivalent.'8
Since I claim in section III that (CJ) can have skeptical consequences without
(UP) having skeptical consequences, I must deny that (CJ) and (UP) are
equivalent. So I must deny that (UP) entails (CJ).
Brueckner sets forth a proof of his claim that (UP') and (CY) (and so (UP)
and (CJ)) are equivalent. The proof consists of a derivation of each principle
from the other. We have already seen how to derive (UP) from (CIJ). If I am
correct, Brueckner's attempt to derive (CY) from (UP') should fail. Here is
Brueckner's account of the derivation:

Assume (UP') and (CJ)'s antecedent. Then it follows that S's evidence for believing that 4

favors 4 over the incompatible V. This by itself is not sufficient to show (CY)'s consequent [S's
evidence justifies not-v]. This is because S's evidence might favor one of two incompatible
hypotheses without being strong enough to justify a belief of either. However, we have
assumed the antecedent of (CJ) in the course of the present attempted derivation, and thus we
have it that S's evidence is sufficient to justify a belief that 4. Now it seems that evidence
justifies not-V].19

As Brueckner shows, from (UP') and the antecedent of (CY), we can derive:

(Q) S's evidence favors 0 over V.

This, he argues, is not by itself sufficient to derive the consequent of (CJ):

(R) S's evidence justifies not-vi.

His reason is that "...S's evidence can favor one of two incompatible
hypotheses without being strong enough to justify a belief of either". Pre-
sumably, the point here is that we cannot get either (R) or

(T) S's evidence justifies 0.

from (Q).
Brueckner goes on to say that what does enable us to derive (R) is that we
are assuming (T) (part of the antecedent of (CJ)) as part of the derivation. But
this is puzzling because we cannot get from (T) to (R) unless we assume
(CJ). We can get from (T) to

17 This derivation assumes the following principle:

For all S, 4, A, if S's evidence justifies 4, and S's evidence justifies not-c, then S's
evidence favors 4 over V.
But presumably, this is a necessary truth.
18 In the text he says they are "virtually equivalent" and sets aside the question of whether
there is any significant difference. But in ft. 7, he sets out a proof that they are equivalent.
19 Op cit., pp. 832-34.

TWO KINDS OF SKEPTICAL ARGUMENTS 151

This content downloaded from


67.249.89.178 on Wed, 08 Jun 2022 00:38:03 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
(U) S's evidence does not justify xg.

given that 0 and vg are incompatible.20 But of course (U) does not entail (R).
Perhaps Brueckner thinks that (R) follows from (T) and (Q) together. But

(Q) follows from (T) and (U). And since (U) follows from (T) (given that 0
and vg are incompatible), (Q) follows from (T) alone (given that 0 and vg ar
incompatible). So (Q) can be of no help in deriving (R). If we cannot derive
(R) from (T), unless we assume (CJ), then we cannot derive (R) from (T) and
(Q), unless we assume (CJ). So the derivation of (CJ) from (UP) fails and
we can reject the claim that (CJ) and (UP) are equivalent.

In section III, I argued that (2C) (My evidence does not favor P over SK)
entails (2D) (My evidence does not justify not-SK) -but not conversely. As
a result, if (UP) has skeptical consequences, so must (CJ). But (CJ) can have
skeptical consequences without (UP) having skeptical consequences.
In section IV, I argued that (CJ) entails (UP)-but not conversely. So if
(2D) has skeptical consequences, so must (2C). But (2C) can have skeptical
consequences without (2D) having skeptical consequences.
What can we conclude about the relative strength of the deductive closure
argument and the underdetermination argument? Consider the two arguments:

(UND)

(1C) If my evidence does not favor P over SK, then my evidence does
not justify P. [from UP]

(2C) My evidence does not favor P over SK. [premise]

(3C) My evidence does not justify P.

(DC)

(1D) If my evidence justifies P, then my evidence justifies not-SK.


[from CJ]

(2D) My evidence does not justify not-SK. [premise]

(3D) My evidence does not justify P.

Each argument has a premise that states an alleged epistemic particular fact
and a premise that states an instance of an alleged epistemic principle.

20 I am assuming that S's evidence cannot justify incompatible propositions. This principle
of course distinct from the closure principle. I discuss it in section VII in connection with
the issue of deriving (UP). Thanks to Tony Brueckner for pointing out to me that, in an
earlier draft, my argument in this section conflicted with this principle.

152 STEWART COHEN

This content downloaded from


67.249.89.178 on Wed, 08 Jun 2022 00:38:03 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Whereas the principle appealed to in (DC) entails the principle appealed to in
(UND), the factual claim in (UND) entails the factual claim in (DC) (given
our restriction). So (UND) appeals to the weaker principle, while making the
stronger factual claim. And (DC) appeals to the stronger principle while mak-
ing the weaker factual claim. So it looks as if each argument has a respect in
which it is more vulnerable relative to the other-(UND) in its reliance on
(2C), the stronger factual claim, and (DC) in its reliance on (ID), an instance
of the stronger principle.
But (ID) cannot really be a weakness of (DC) relative to (UND). For the
premises of (UND) entail (iD). The denial of (ID) says that my evidence
justifies me in believing P but does not justify me in believing not-SK.
This, of course, entails the denial of (3C). So the denial of (ID) entails the
denial of (3C) and so (3C) entails (ID). But the conjunction of (IC) and (2C)
entails (3C). So the conjunction of (iC) and (2C) entails (ID).
Here is the derivation of (ID) from (iC) and (2C):

(1) My evidence does not favor P over SK. [2C]

(2) If my evidence does not favor P over SK, then my evidence does
not justify me in believing P. [1C]

(3) My evidence justifies me in believing P but my evidence does


not justify me in believing not-SK. [denial of (ID), assume for
reduction]

(4) My evidence justifies me in believing P. [from 3]

(5) My evidence does not justify me in believing P. [from 1, 2]

We have just seen that the conjunction of the premises of (UND) entail
premise (ID) of (DC). In section III, we saw that premise (2C) of (UND)
entails (given our restriction) premise (2D) of (DC). So we can now see that
the premises of (UND) entail both premises of (DC). But though the
premises of (DC) entail premise (iC) of (UND) (since (ID) entails (iC)),
they do not entail premise (2C) of (UND). Since both arguments are valid, it
follows that (UND) is a sound argument only if (DC) is-but not conversely.
Thus, (UND) can be refuted without refuting (DC), but (DC) cannot be
refuted without refuting (UND).2' In this way, (DC) is the stronger argumen
How significant is the greater strength of (DC)? This will depend, in part
on whether there actually are any serious antiskeptical arguments against
(UND) that do not count against (DC). Though a thorough discussion of this
issue would take us far beyond the scope of this paper, there are two kinds of
arguments worth considering briefly.

21 I am assuming that refuting a valid argument entails showing that one of its premises is
false.

TWO KINDS OF SKEPTICAL ARGUMENTS 153

This content downloaded from


67.249.89.178 on Wed, 08 Jun 2022 00:38:03 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
According to the first kind of antiskeptical strategy, pragmatic criteria like
simplicity or conservatism play a role in determining what hypotheses our
evidence supports. These arguments maintain that our ordinary claims (or
hypotheses) about the external world fare better than skeptical hypotheses
when measured against these pragmatic criteria. If this is correct, then insofar
as we are counting these criteria as relevant to what our evidence supports,
our evidence, in general, favors external world hypotheses over skeptical
hypotheses. So suppose P is simpler than SK. Then given our assumption
that considerations of simplicity play a role in determining what my evidence
supports, it follows that all things considered, my evidence does favor P over
SK. That is, (2C) (My evidence does not favor P over SK) is false.
Should we go on to say that because P is in some way simpler than SK,
my evidence justifies me in believing not-SK? It is not at all clear that we
should. Our concern is whether we are justified in believing not-SK to a
degree sufficient for knowing not-SK. And it strikes me as a defensible view
to hold that considerations of simplicity tip the evidential scales in favor of P
without tipping them to the extent that my evidence justifies not-SK to that
degree. So even if we suppose that in virtue of pragmatic criteria like sim-
plicity my evidence favors P over SK (the denial of (2C)), it may still be that
(2D) (My evidence does not justify not-SK) is not thereby threatened. The
upshot is that antiskeptical arguments that appeal to pragmatic criteria pose a
greater threat to the underdetermination argument (UND) than to the closure
argument (DC).22
The second kind of antiskeptical argument I want to consider focuses on
the role of global skeptical alternatives in classic skeptical arguments. Con-
sider the hypothesis that I am a brain-in-a-vat or the hypothesis that I am
deceived by a Cartesian demon. These alternatives are global in that they
compete with any proposition I claim to know about the external world.23
Many philosophers-Carnap, Wittgenstein, Davidson, Putnam, to name a
few-have objected to skeptical arguments on the grounds that to suppose

22 We might stipulate that pragmatic criteria like simplicity are not relevant, strictly speak-
ing, to evidential justification. On this way of viewing matters, neither (2C) nor (2D) is
threatened by an appeal to pragmatic criteria, as they concern only evidential
justification.
If this is how we view matters then I could still make my point with regard to skepti-
cal arguments analogous to (UND) and (DC) that proceed in terms of justification all
things considered, i.e., both evidential and non-evidential justification. The appeal to
pragmatic criteria would pose a greater threat to the analogue of (2C) than the analogue
of (2D).
23 This depends slightly on how we formulate SK and the propositions about the external
world. The way I have formulated SK, it competes with proposition about the external
world like I see a table but not with propositions like There is a table. We could build into
SK that I am a deceived brain-in-a-vat to make it conflict with proposition of the latter
kind as well.

154 STEWART COHEN

This content downloaded from


67.249.89.178 on Wed, 08 Jun 2022 00:38:03 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
that I am deceived in the way global skeptical alternatives entail is somehow
incoherent or self-refuting.
We could however sidestep this kind of antiskeptical strategy by construct-
ing a skeptical argument that proceeds solely in terms of restricted skeptical
alternatives. Alternatives of this kind compete only with a restricted class of
knowledge claims. For example, the alternative that my car has been stolen
competes only with propositions I claim to know concerning the location of
my car, who has been in it recently, etc. Now, for almost any proposition I
claim to know, we could devise some restricted alternative to it. So we could
make the case for skepticism (less elegantly) by a series of arguments, each
of which appeals to some restricted alternative. This kind of skeptical argu-
ment, though perhaps not as far reaching as the classic skeptical argument,
would still support the conclusion that we fail to know much of what we
ordinarily take ourselves to know. Moreover, it would be immune to the kind
of antiskeptical argument that attacks the coherence of the global skeptical
alternatives.24
This bears directly on the issue of the relative strength of (UND) and
(DC). Although plausible deductive closure arguments can be constructed us-
ing either kind of skeptical alternative, underdetermination arguments require
global skeptical alternatives. For though our evidence justifies us to some
degree in believing restricted skeptical alternatives are false, it is very plausi-
ble to suppose it does not justify us to the degree necessary for knowing
skeptical alternatives are false. But it is not very plausible to suppose that
our evidence does not favor the mundane propositions we claim to know over
restricted skeptical alternatives. For example, while it is very plausible to
suppose that my evidence does not justify me to the degree necessary for
knowing my car has not been stolen, it is not very plausible to suppose that
my evidence does not favor the hypothesis that my car is parked in my garage
over the hypothesis that my car has been stolen. The fact is that I have fairly
good statistical evidence that favors the former hypothesis over the latter.
Nonetheless, it is natural to balk at saying I know my car has not been
stolen.25
What this shows is that premise (2C) of (UND) is plausible only for
global alternatives, unlike premise (2D) of (DC) which is plausible for both
global and restricted alternatives. Because underdetermination arguments must
appeal to global alternatives, they cannot avoid the kind of antiskeptical
response that specifically attacks the coherence of global skeptical alterna-

24 This kind of skeptical strategy is discussed by Jonathan Vogel in "Are There Counter-
examples to the Closure Principle?" in Doubting: Contemporary Perspectives on Skepti-
cism, Michael D. Roth and Glenn Ross, eds. (Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers,
1990), pp. 20-23.
25 Am I justified in believing that my car has been stolen? Of course, I am justified to some
degree-but not, I am inclined to say, to the degree necessary for knowing.

TWO KINDS OF SKEPTICAL ARGUMENTS 155

This content downloaded from


67.249.89.178 on Wed, 08 Jun 2022 00:38:03 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
tives. So if one of these responses succeeds, it would refute any underdeter-
mination argument while leaving intact the deductive closure argument which
proceeds in terms of restricted alternatives.
So how significant is the greater strength of (DC) over (UND)? Though
the two kinds of antiskeptical strategies we have considered pose a greater
threat to (UND) than to (DC), we have not taken up the question of how suc-
cessful either of these strategies is. And to do so would take us far beyond the
scope of this paper.26

VI

Given that any refutation of (DC) would also be a refutation of (UND), we


might wonder whether any appeal to (UND) is dialectically superfluous. Here,
however, we must distinguish between the refutability of an argument and the
cogency of an argument. Though the soundness of (UND) is linked to the
soundness of (DC), it does not follow that the cogency of (UND) is linked to
the cogency of (DC). (DC) may fail to be cogent even though it has not,
strictly speaking, been refuted. Suppose when I consider (DC) by itself, I find
its premises to have not very much plausibility or, at least, to have not
enough plausibility to withstand the conflict with our ordinary claims to
know.27 It does not follow that I must conclude that the conjunction of those
premises is false and therefore the conjunction of the premises of (UND) is
false (since they entail the premises of (DC)). For suppose further that I find
the premises of (UND) to have considerable plausibility or at least enough
plausibility to withstand the conflict with our ordinary claims to know. Then
I will have reason to accept the premises of (UND) and, because they are
entailed by the premises of (UND), the premises of (DC) as well. In such a
case, (UND) would be critical for establishing the skeptical threat.
Under this scenario, even though the soundness of (UND) requires the
soundness of (DC), the cogency of (DC) requires the cogency of (UND). Thus
(DC) would be the superfluous argument-a kind of dialectical epiphe-
nomenon.
Even if I find the premises of (DC) to be at least as compelling as the
premises of (UND), it does not follow that (UND) is superfluous. For (UND)
would still provide an independent route to skepticism. Certainly an addi-
tional argument for skepticism exacerbates the skeptical problem. If either
argument is undermined, the other might remain as a skeptical threat.
Though, as we have noted, in order for (UND) to survive the failure of (DC),

26 My own view is that neither kind of antiskeptical argument is very convincing.


27 Sometimes we reject skeptical arguments because their premises are less plausible than
the claim that we know things about the external world. For example, that is the fallibilist
response to the skeptical argument based on the premise that my evidence gives me
knowledge of P only if my evidence entails P.

156 STEWART COHEN

This content downloaded from


67.249.89.178 on Wed, 08 Jun 2022 00:38:03 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
the premises of (DC) would have to be undermined in a way that did not
show them to be false.

VII

Let's return to the original question of this paper. What is the relative
significance of the underdetermination principle (UP) and the deductive clo-
sure principle (CJ) for formulating skeptical arguments? Assuming that both
principles have considerable intuitive plausibility, it now looks as if neither
principle can be said to be superfluous in the case for skepticism. Each prin-
ciple figures centrally in an independently motivated argument for skepticism.
Measured by refutability, (DC) is the stronger argument. Measured by
cogency, however, it need not be the stronger argument. Which (if either)
argument is the more cogent will depend on nothing more than which (if
either) has the more compelling premises.
One wrinkle remains. We have seen that (UP) can be derived from (CJ).
Suppose it turned out that (UP) depends for its intuitive appeal on being so
derivable. Then (UP) would not provide an independent motivation for the
skeptical problem. If this were true, we would have to conclude that the
appeal to (UP) is superfluous, and that the skeptical problem is, at root, a
problem about deductive closure.
Does the intuitive appeal of (UP) depend on its being derivable from (CJ)?
This is, to a certain extent, a psychological question. Certainly it does not
follow from the fact that (UP) can be derived from other principles that its
intuitive plausibility derives from those other principles. Perhaps the intu-
itive plausibility of (UP) does not depend on any other principles.
Suppose, however, that the plausibility of (UP) does derive from more
basic principles. It still does not follow that its plausibility depends on (CJ).
For there are other ways to derive (UP). Think about what (UP) says:

(UP) For all S, 0, Ag, if S's evidence does not favor 0 over some
incompatible hypothesis Ag, then S's evidence does not justify 0.

The antecedent of the conditional (embedded in the principle) is a conjunction:


S's evidence does not favor 0 over A, and 0 and v are incompatible. So per-
haps we can see (UP) as deriving from a principle about evidential favoring
and a principle about incompatible hypotheses. That is in fact how the deriva-
tion of (UP) in section III proceeds. (CJ) (or its equivalent formulation (CJ))
is a principle about incompatible hypotheses and the other principle we
needed to assume was a principle about evidential favoring.28
But even supposing that (UND) is derived from a principle about eviden-
tial favoring and a principle about incompatible hypotheses, it need not be

28 See my note 17.

TWO KINDS OF SKEPTICAL ARGUMENTS 157

This content downloaded from


67.249.89.178 on Wed, 08 Jun 2022 00:38:03 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
thought of as deriving from (CJ). Here is another way to think of it: Suppose

S's evidence does not favor 0 over Ag. This does not by itself have the conse-
quence that S's evidence does not justify 0. Perhaps S's evidence justifies
both 0 and Ag. What follows from the assumption that S's evidence does not
favor 0 over vg is that if S's evidence justifies 0, then it justifies w:

(FAV) For all S, 0, Ag, if S's evidence does not favor 0 over vg and S's
evidence justifies 0, then S's evidence justifies Ay.

But the fact that 0 and vg are incompatible rules out the possibility that S's
evidence justifies both 0 and A:

(INC) For all S, 0, A, if S's evidence justifies 0, and 0 entails not-ei,


then S's evidence does not justify Ag.

Given (FAV) and (INC), if S's evidence does not favor 0 over vg and 0 and xv
are incompatible, then S's evidence does not justify 0. That is, the conjunc-
tion of (INC) and (FAV) entails (UND).29 Moreover, neither (INC) nor
(UND) follows from (CJ).30 Given the intuitive plausibility of (INC) and
(FAV), we can conclude that the intuitive appeal of (UP) does not depend on
its being derivable from (CJ).3'

29 Here's the proof:

(1) If my evidence justifies 4, and 4 entails not-e, then my evidence does not jus-
tify v [INC]

(2) If my evidence does not favor 4 over A, and my evidence justifies 4, then my
evidence justifies V. [FAV]

(3) My evidence does not favor 4 over v and 4 entails not-c and my evidence
justifies 4 [denial of UP, assume for reductio]

(4) My evidence does not favor 4 over v and my evidence justifies 4. [from 3]

(5) My evidence justifies V. [from 2, 4]

(6) My evidence does not justify 4 or 4 does not entail not-v. [from 1, 5]

(7) 0 entails not-e [from 3]

(8) My evidence does not justify Q. [from 6, 7]

(9) My evidence justifies 4. [from 3]


30 (CJ) entails (INC) given that if S's evidence justifies 4, then S's evidence does not justify
not-?. But that's just an instance of (INC). So it would be hard to argue that (INC)
depends on (CJ) for its plausibility.
31 This is not to say that there could not be someone for whom the intuitive appeal of
depends on its derivability from (CJ). It is just that such a person would have to not accept
either (INC) or (FAV). And it is hard to see how one could fail to accept either.
Of course, even if one does not accept either (INC) or (FAV), it does not follow that
one's acceptance of (UP) depends on its derivability from (CJ).

158 STEWART COHEN

This content downloaded from


67.249.89.178 on Wed, 08 Jun 2022 00:38:03 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
If this is correct, then the underdetermination principle and the deductive
closure principle do provide independent motivations for the skeptical prob-
lem.32, 33

32 Just as (ID) is entailed by (IC) and (2C), so (CJ) is entailed by (UP) and a generalization
of (2C):

(2CG) For any (), my evidence does not favor 4 over SK.

(2C) is just an arbitrary instance of (2CG). And (UP) and (2CG) entail the generalization
of (3C):

(3CG) For any (O), my evidence does not justify me in believing Q.

And (3CG) entails (CJ) in just the same way (IC) and (2C) entail (ID).
Is it plausible, therefore, to suppose that the intuitive appeal of (CJ) depends on the
appeal of (UP)? If that were true, our acceptance of (CJ) would depend on our accep-
tance of what is asserted in (3CG). But that is just the generalization of what (3D), the
conclusion of (DC), asserts as well. (CJ) is suitable as the justification for premise (ID)
in (DC) precisely because its considerable appeal is independent of our acceptance of
the conclusion of (DC).
33 I would like to thank Brad Armendt, Tom Blackson, David Cowles, Greg Fitch, Ted
Guleserian, Bernie Kobes, John O'Leary-Hawthorne Steve Reynolds, and Jonathan
Vogel for helpful discussion of these issues.

TWO KINDS OF SKEPTICAL ARGUMENTS 159

This content downloaded from


67.249.89.178 on Wed, 08 Jun 2022 00:38:03 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms

You might also like