Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 44

From Action to Ethics - A Pluralistic

Approach to Reasons and


Responsibility Constantine Sandis
Visit to download the full and correct content document:
https://ebookmass.com/product/from-action-to-ethics-a-pluralistic-approach-to-reason
s-and-responsibility-constantine-sandis/
More products digital (pdf, epub, mobi) instant
download maybe you interests ...

A Guide to Sustainable Corporate Responsibility: From


Theory to Action Caroline D. Ditlev-Simonsen

https://ebookmass.com/product/a-guide-to-sustainable-corporate-
responsibility-from-theory-to-action-caroline-d-ditlev-simonsen/

(eBook PDF) Business and Society: A Strategic Approach


to Social Responsibility & Ethics, 7th edition

https://ebookmass.com/product/ebook-pdf-business-and-society-a-
strategic-approach-to-social-responsibility-ethics-7th-edition/

Reasons in Action: A Reductionist Account of


Intentional Action Ingmar Persson

https://ebookmass.com/product/reasons-in-action-a-reductionist-
account-of-intentional-action-ingmar-persson/

Reasons to Pass: A Guide to Making Fewer and Better


Investments Ralph Birchmeier

https://ebookmass.com/product/reasons-to-pass-a-guide-to-making-
fewer-and-better-investments-ralph-birchmeier/
From Perception to Communication: A Theory of Types for
Action and Meaning Robin Cooper

https://ebookmass.com/product/from-perception-to-communication-a-
theory-of-types-for-action-and-meaning-robin-cooper/

Environmental Sociology: From Analysis to Action 3rd


Edition, (Ebook PDF)

https://ebookmass.com/product/environmental-sociology-from-
analysis-to-action-3rd-edition-ebook-pdf/

A Thermo-Economic Approach to Energy from Waste Anand


Ramanathan

https://ebookmass.com/product/a-thermo-economic-approach-to-
energy-from-waste-anand-ramanathan/

A Scientific Approach to Ethics: Developing Greater


Respect for Ethics in Business and Society 1st Edition
Maxim Storchevoy (Auth.)

https://ebookmass.com/product/a-scientific-approach-to-ethics-
developing-greater-respect-for-ethics-in-business-and-
society-1st-edition-maxim-storchevoy-auth/

42 Reasons to Hate the Universe (And One Reason Not To)


Chris Ferrie

https://ebookmass.com/product/42-reasons-to-hate-the-universe-
and-one-reason-not-to-chris-ferrie/
From Action to Ethics
Also available from Bloomsbury:

Advances in Experimental Philosophy of Action, edited by Paul Henne and


Samuel Murray
Certainty in Action, by Danièle Moyal-Sharrock
Wittgenstein’s Lion, by Constantine Sandis
Reframing Ethics Through Dialectics, by Michael Steinmann
From Action to Ethics

A Pluralistic Approach to Reasons


and Responsibility

Constantine Sandis
BLOOMSBURY ACADEMIC
Bloomsbury Publishing Plc
50 Bedford Square, London, WC1B 3DP, UK
1385 Broadway, New York, NY 10018, USA
29 Earlsfort Terrace, Dublin 2, Ireland

BLOOMSBURY, BLOOMSBURY ACADEMIC and the Diana logo are trademarks of


Bloomsbury Publishing Plc

First published in Great Britain 2024

Copyright © Constantine Sandis, 2024

Constantine Sandis has asserted his right under the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act,
1988, to be identified as Author of this work.

For legal purposes the Acknowledgements on p. ix constitute an extension


of this copyright page.

Cover design by Constantine Sandis and Louise Dugdale

All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced or transmitted in any
form or by any means, electronic or mechanical, including photocopying, recording, or
any information storage or retrieval system, without prior permission in writing from the
publishers.

Bloomsbury Publishing Plc does not have any control over, or responsibility for, any third-
party websites referred to or in this book. All internet addresses given in this book were
correct at the time of going to press. The author and publisher regret any inconvenience
caused if addresses have changed or sites have ceased to exist, but can accept no
responsibility for any such changes.

A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library.

A catalog record for this book is available from the Library of Congress.

ISBN: HB: 978-1-3502-3511-3


ePDF: 978-1-3502-3512-0
eBook: 978-1-3502-3513-7

Typeset by Deanta Global Publishing Services, Chennai, India

To find out more about our authors and books visit www​.bloomsbury​.com and
sign up for our newsletters.


For Calypso
who can act for reasons but hasn’t quite made it all
the way to ethics.
But what first, Debbie, attracted you to the millionaire Paul Daniels?
Mrs Merton
Contents

List of figures viii


Preface and acknowledgments ix

Introduction: Actions, reasons, and ethics 1

Part I Action

1 Action cubes and traces 9


2 What is it to do nothing? 22
3 Are we superhuman or are we dancer? Action and will in the novels of
Anthony Powell 35
4 Reasoning to action 49
5 How to act against your better judgement 55

Part II Reasons

6 Dretske on the causation of behaviour 67


7 The objects of action explanation 78
8 Verbal reports and ‘real’ reasons: Confabulation and conflation 88
9 Can action explanations ever be non-factive? 101
10 Are reasons like shampoo? 113

Part III Ethics

11 Gods and mental states: The causation of action in ancient tragedy and
modern philosophy of mind 127
12 Motivated by the gods: Compartmentalized agency and responsibility 146
13 The man who mistook his Handlung for a Tat: Hegel on Oedipus and
other tragic Thebans 158
14 The doing and the deed: Action in normative ethics 175
15 Ethics and action theory: An unhappy divorce 188

Appendix: Basic actions and individuation 203


Notes 209
References 237
Index 265
Figures

1 Action Necker Cube (Abstract) 12


2 Action Necker Cube (Concrete) 14
3 Moving my body 72
4 Turning my head 74
5 Raising my arm 76
6 Indicating stimuli 77
Preface and acknowledgments

The essays in this book draw on material previously published between 2008 and
2022. I should like thank all of the publishers for their permission to re-use the relevant
material. I hereby acknowledge their original sources in chronological order, which
tells a different story from the one presented in the book:

‘How to Act Against Your Better Judgement’, Philosophical Frontiers, 3 (2) (2008):
111–24.

‘Dretske on the Causation of Behaviour’, Behavior and Philosophy, 36 (2008):


71–85. © Cambridge Center for Behavioral Studies. Reprinted with permission from
CCBS.

‘Gods and Mental States’, in Constantine Sandis (ed.), New Essays on the Explanation of
Action, 358–85, Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, 2009. © Springer Nature. Reprinted
with permission from Springer Nature.

‘Basic Actions and Individuation’, in Timothy O’Connor and Constantine Sandis


(eds.), A Companion to the Philosophy of Action, 10–17, Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell, 2010.
©Wiley-Blackwell; reprinted with kind permission.

‘The Man Who Mistook his Handlung for a Tat’, Bulletin of the Hegel Society of Great
Britain, No. 62 (2010): 35–60. © The Hegel Society of Great Britain 2010; reprinted
with kind permission.

‘The Objects of Action Explanation’, Ratio, 25 (3; Sep 2012): 326–44. ©Wiley-
Blackwell; reprinted with kind permission.

‘Can Action Explanations Ever Be Non-Factive?’, in Brad Hooker, Margaret Little,


and David Backhurst (eds.), Thinking about Reasons: Themes from the Philosophy of
Jonathan Dancy, 29–49, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2013. © Oxford Publishing
Limited. Reproduced with permission of the Licensor through PLSclear.

‘Verbal Reports and “Real Reasons”: Confabulation and Conflation’, Ethical Theory
and Moral Practice, 18 (2), 267-80. © Springer Nature. Reproduced with permission
from Springer Nature.
x Preface and Acknowledgments

‘Motivated by the Gods’, in Andrei Buckareff, Carlos Moya, and Sergi Rosell (eds.),
Agency and Responsibility, 209–25, Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, 2015. © Springer
Nature. Reproduced with permission from Springer Nature.

‘Are We Superhuman or Are We Dancer?’, Proceedings of the 7th Biennial Anthony


Powell Conference, AP Society Press, 2016, 25–41. First published by The Anthony
Powell Society; reprinted with kind permission.

‘The Doing and the Deed’, Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement, 80 (July 2017):
105–26. © The Royal Institute of Philosophy and the contributors 2017; reprinted with
kind permission.

‘Are Reasons Like Shampoo?’, in Gunnar Schumann (ed.), Explanation in Action


Theory and Historiography: Causal and Teleological Approaches, 146–64, Abingdon:
Routledge, 2019. © Taylor & Francis Group. Reprinted by permission of the publisher
(Taylor & Francis Ltd.).

‘Reasoning to Action’, Philosophical Explorations, 23 (1; 2020): 180–6. © Taylor & Francis
Group. Reprinted by permission of the publisher (Taylor & Francis Ltd.).

‘What Is It to Do Nothing?’, in Veronica Rodriguez-Blanco and George Pavlakos


(eds.), Negligence, Omissions and Responsibility: Reflecting on Philosophy of Action,
187–204, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2021. © Cambridge University
Press 2022; reprinted with kind permission.

‘Action Cubes and Traces’, in Carla Bagnoli (ed.), Time in Action: The Temporal
Structure of Rational Agency and Practical Thought, 32–51, Abingdon: Routledge,
2021. © Taylor & Francis Group. Reprinted by permission of the publisher
(Taylor & Francis Ltd.).

‘Ethics and Action Theory’, in Roger Teichmann (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of
Elizabeth Anscombe, 469-489, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2022. © Oxford
Publishing Limited. Reproduced with permission of the Licensor through PLSclear.

While I’ve tried to keep any repetition of ideas to a minimum, some inevitable overlap
remains so as to enable the reader to dip into any given essay without prerequisites.
I have avoided the inclusion of any essays that are readily available online via free
open access, or which appear in other English collections of my work. I have also
chosen not to include any co-written essays. Modified versions of nine of the essays
listed above have been published (alongside six others) in a French translation by Rémi
Clot-Goudard as Raisons et responsabilité - Essais de philosophie de l'action (Ithaque,
2021; reprinted Éliott 2023). I cannot thank Rémi enough for his philosophical and
organizational help.
I would also like to thank Colleen Coalter, Becky Holland, Suzie Nash, Ben O'Hagan
and Liza Thompson at Bloomsbury, for all their help and patience; four anonymous

Preface and Acknowledgments xi

referees for the press for their encouragement and invaluable feedback; my wife Louise
Chapman for standing by me in sickness and in health; and our fellow Lex Academic
team members, Jennifer Swift and Jessica Oliver, for their unflinching support.
The raw material for this volume was published over a period of fifteen years, having
first been presented at more than one hundred seminars, workshops and conferences.
I hope that all of those who helped me to improve it will forgive me for not collating
all of my original acknowledgments here. I would be remiss, however, to not mention
Andreas Lind for his ongoing encouragement and advice during this time. I also
benefited from Visiting Fellowships at the Helsinki Collegium for Advanced Studies
(2009 and 2014), Centre de Recherche en Ethique in Montréal (2014–15 and 2018–19)
and the Center for Ethics and Public Affairs at the Murphy Institute at Tulane University
(2018–19), as well as from sabbaticals at Oxford Brookes University and the University
of Hertfordshire, financial support from the Spanish Ministry project ‘Modal Aspects
of Materialist Realism’ (2007–10), the NOMOS Network for Applied Philosophy
projects ‘Alternatives, Belief and Action’ (2010–12) and ‘Perspectival Thoughts and
Facts’ (2010–14), and the ‘Santander Research Project Award’ (2012–13).

The book is dedicated to Calypso, who will not read it.


CS
Poole, July 2023
xii
Introduction
Actions, reasons, and ethics

Prologue
Action theory without ethics is empty; ethics without action theory is blind. The
essays collected here accordingly stand for a symbiotic approach to philosophical and
psychological accounts of (i) actions, (ii) their explanation and (iii) their moral status.
Each individual essay takes us from action to ethics, broadly construed. But the essays
also move collectively in this direction.
The book is divided into three corresponding parts. The first, ‘Action’
(Chapters 1–5), concerns the nature of action and its relation to agents. The second,
‘Reasons’ (Chapters 6–10), considers the reasons for which we act and how these relate to
other explanatory factors. The final part, ‘Ethics’ (Chapters 11–15), turns to questions in
moral psychology and normative ethics, approaching them from the perspective of the
book’s earlier discussions. A brief appendix, ‘Basic Actions and Individuation’, presents
a critical overview of the main positions on action individuation and the search for the
most basic form of action. These enquiries are not conducted ahistorically, but via an
intertwining with an eclectic history of ideas, from The Bhagavad Gītā and Sophocles
to Freud, Anthony Powell, Anscombe and Ricœur. It is tempting to describe the result
as a kind of applied philosophy of action, but the influence between action theory and
that which is extraneous to it runs in both directions.
Given how strongly interconnected I take the book’s main topics to be, it should
come as no surprise that its three parts are not so much divided by thematic boundaries
as they are united through investigatory fluidity. How can we offer accounts of either
reasons or rightness without a solid grasp of action concepts? Conversely, if an ontology
of action is to have any merit, then it needs to accommodate certain psychological and
ethical constraints.
On the one hand, we can conceive of actions as repeatables that can be done
intentionally or unintentionally; voluntarily or involuntarily; rationally or irrationally;
rightly or wrongly; individually or collectively; and so on. On the other, there exists
an equally valid conception according to which they are spatio-temporal particulars
with concrete causes and effects. What is the connection between these two senses of
‘action’, and how should it inform motivational psychology and ethical theory? These
are the questions that this book seeks to answer.
2 From Action to Ethics

I. Action
Part I develops a distinctive understanding of the relation of doings to things
done. This serves as a leitmotif throughout the rest of the book. In doing so, it also
carves out a space for agency and volition within the natural order of things. The
first chapter, ‘Action cubes and traces’, considers Paul Ricœur’s powerful suggestion
that we should understand things done as marks left on time by the events of our
acting, just as things written down are residual traces of writing events. While his
resulting account of actions as cubical volumes in space-time, which may be reached
from a plurality of perspectives, is an insightful one, I maintain that we would do
better to conceive of our deeds not as traces but as the leaving of traces, a distinction
with surprisingly important repercussions in both moral psychology and normative
ethics.
One corollary of the cubical account of action may be traced back to the
Bhagavadian view that all action contains inaction, and vice versa. Guided by this,
Chapter 2 (‘What is it to do nothing?’) argues that we should reject any theory that
rests on the metaphysical assumption that actions—or even their characterizations—
can be neatly divided into positive acts of doing and so-called ‘negative’ acts of
omitting, refraining and neglecting. I proceed to re-evaluate the doctrine of doing
and allowing and related puzzles concerning moral responsibility in the light of this
rejection.
Chapters 3–5 explore the relation between actions and their agents. ‘Are we
superhuman or are we dancer?’ does so by way of the novels of Anthony Powell.
Powell’s characters are satirically partitioned between agents and patients, with many
of those who at first appear to belong to the former set par excellence being ultimately
shown up. Powell’s novels serve as a comic warning of the perils – both theoretical and
practical – of overestimating our agential capacities.
‘Reasoning to action’ considers Jonathan Dancy’s recent defence of an ‘actionalist’
conception of practical reasoning. This has its roots in Aristotle’s thought that we can
equally reason from our current beliefs to action as we can to a new belief. In recent
decades this has been challenged by cognitivists and intentionalists who, respectively,
claim that practical reasoning can only result in either normative beliefs or intention.
My own version of the ‘actionalist’ conclusion holds that the aim and issue of
practical reasoning are logically connected in such a way that reasoning cannot result
in action without also resulting in some form of belief in action. This raises questions
about the very possibility of akrasia, which is the topic of Chapter 5, ‘How to act
against your better judgement’. Those who object to Davidson’s understanding of
how akrasia is possible tend to argue that he is committed to claiming that akratic
agents must in some sense hold contradictory judgements in deliberation. I try to
show that while there is nothing paradoxical in what Davidson says, his ‘solution’
only deals with that form of akrasia that Aristotle calls propeteia (rashness), at the
expense of the more puzzling case of astheneia (weakness). I conclude that, despite
certain failings stemming from its motivational internalism, Davidson’s theory is
essentially equipped with the right distinctions to demonstrate the possibility of
genuine astheneia.

Introduction 3

II. Reasons
This part of the book moves from reasoning to reasons. Debates about the ontology
of reasons are frequently conducted with surprising independence from questions
concerning the nature of action and its explanation. This leads to a number of
unfortunate conflations between the reasons we act for, the reasons that explain why we
acted as we did, and the reasons that motivated us to so act. The chapters in Part II may
be viewed as an exercise in analytic deconstructivism. They aim to demonstrate why
there can be no coherent analysis of ‘reason for action’ whereby it can simultaneously
act as a consideration, explanans, and motive or motivational force. Put more positively,
we should be conceptual pluralists about both actions and their reasons. I argue for this
explicitly in ‘The objects of action explanation’, which serves as a transition between the
first two parts of the volume. The chapter begins by distinguishing between different
conceptions of behaviour before exploring an accompanying variety of things that
‘action explanation’ may plausibly amount to.
Chapter 6, ‘Dretske on the causation of behaviour’, introduces Fred Dretske’s unjustly
neglected distinction between the triggering and structuring causes of behaviour.
Dretske maintains that intentional human action is triggered by perceptual events
(‘causes’) but structured by representational facts (‘reasons’). On this view, actions are
not events but, rather, causal processes of one event triggering another. This chapter
seeks to show that while Dretske’s causalism is considerably more persuasive than the
standard Davidsonian alternative, it ultimately fails to capture what is distinctive about
intentional action and its explanation.
If, however, we altogether abandon causalist accounts of action explanation, then
does this not render reasons epiphenomenal? The remaining chapters in the middle
section of the book seek to address this question from different angles. ‘Verbal reports
and “real reasons”’ (Chapter 8) examines the relation between the various forces that
underlie human action and our verbal reports about our reasons for acting as we did.
Its unabashed conclusion is that much of the psychological literature on confabulations
conflates a number of distinct motivational factors. The most interesting part of the
confabulation literature, then, is that many experimental psychologists are themselves
guilty of confabulation in their accounts of why their subjects behaved as they did.
I contend that subjects frequently give correct answers to questions about the
considerations they acted upon, while remaining largely unaware of why they take
themselves to have such reasons to act. Pari passu, experimental psychologists are
wrong to think that they have shown our everyday reason talk to be systematically
confused. This is significant because reason-ascriptions can affect characterizations of
action that are morally and legally relevant (a theme I return to in Part III). But far
from rendering empirical research on confabulations invalid, my re-interpretation of
it unclouds its true insights into human nature.
Chapter 9, ‘Can action explanations ever be non-factive?’, suggests that, although
anti-psychologists such as Dancy are right to contest the commonplace view that
agential reasons are psychological states, they throw the baby out with the bathwater
in concluding that reason-giving explanations must therefore be non-factive. An
apparent corollary of this view is the paradoxical thesis that the reasons for which we
4 From Action to Ethics

act are actually incapable of explaining why we act. I revisit this thesis in ‘Are reasons
like shampoo?’ (Chapter 10). Debates in ‘reasonology’ typically arise when theorists,
in the grip of different pictures, enforce Procrustean constraints on attempts to carve
nature at its proverbial joints. One such picture is that of a reason as a consideration
we act in the light of. Another is that of a reason as something that motivates us. A
third is that of reasons as explanations of processes or events. It is an illusion to think
that these distinct conceptions can be united under a single concept of a reason: one
whose correct analysis reveals a hidden triple formula. We would do better to embrace
a pluralism that allows for different concepts of a reason for different purposes:
psychological, socio-historical and ethical. Once we come to accept this, the vexed
question of whether reasons are causes dissolves.

III. Ethics
The chapter in the previous section have been guided by the thought that we cannot
sensibly divorce theories of action explanation from accounts of what it is to act in the
first place. In this final part of the book, I make the parallel suggestion that one cannot
simply plug in one’s favourite account of action into ethical debates without seriously
affecting the plausibility of any given theory.
The first three chapters of Part III (11–13) concentrate on the relation between action
explanation and moral responsibility. ‘Gods and mental states’ argues that, contrary
to popular opinion, ancient tragedy presents us with a percipient understanding of
human agency and responsibility that is preferable to most contemporary accounts.
This is because the ancients were wise to separate the motivation of action from its
causal production. ‘Motivated by the Gods’ looks to both Greek tragedy and Theodore
Dreiser’s An American Tragedy for insights into the ownership of motivational factors
that are not fully under our control. The liability for actions performed under such alien
influences, I maintain, is not merely causal but moral and psychological. ‘The man who
mistook his Handlung for a Tat’ acts as a bridge between the previous two papers and
the final pair (which focus on the importance of action theory for normative ethics).
This chapter compares the aforementioned distinction between doings and things
done to Hegel’s tripartite presentation of action under the aspects of Handlung, Tat
and Tun. I try to show that the latter anticipates the complex moral epistemology of H.
A. Prichard and W. D. Ross in its pluralistic approach to luck and imputation.
Chapter 14, ‘The doing and the deed’, makes a case for the importance of the
aforementioned distinctions to central questions in normative ethics. The lack of
attention paid by moral theory to the philosophy of action is striking when compared,
for example, to that paid by epistemology to the notion of belief. I demonstrate how
much more effectively we can steer through the debates between consequentialism,
deontology, virtue ethics and so on, once armed with a proper pluralistic
understanding of action concepts. Consider, for example, the debate concerning
whether or not intention matters to right action. It is prima facie unclear what it would
mean for intention to matter to the rightness or wrongness of a (repeatable) thing
done. By contrast, it is highly implausible that intention does not matter to the moral
evaluation of an agent’s particular doing of something. I contend, inter alia, that the

Introduction 5

notion of right action most amenable to virtue ethics is different from that used by, say,
consequentialists.
The final chapter, ‘Ethics and action theory’, looks back at mid-twentieth-century
attempts to think through issues in moral philosophy via questions about action. It
is a sad irony that this approach was effectively as a result of Anscombe’s influential
1958 article ‘Modern Moral Philosophy’, in which she explicitly makes a case for it.
Having offered an analysis of how we got to where we are today, the chapter ends on
a more optimistic note for the future of action in ethics, for which this book serves
merely as a groundwork.

Epilogue
In a 2021 interview conducted by Chris Heath for GQ magazine’s ‘Happiness Project’,
filmmaker David Lynch found himself distinguishing between the doing of things, and
the work done:

I’m just kind of happy in the doing of things. [. . .] Getting an idea, or realizing an
idea, working on a painting or working on a piece of sculpture, working on a film.
[. . .] One thing I’ve noticed is that many of us, we do what we call work, for a goal,
for a result. And in the doing, it’s not that much happiness. And yet that’s our life
going by [. . .] It doesn’t matter what your work is, you just get happy in the work,
you get happy in the little things and the big things. And if the result isn’t what you
dreamed of, it doesn’t kill you if you enjoyed the doing of it. It’s important that we
enjoy the doing of our life. (Heath 2021)

This is not a book about happiness, but for the most part I have enjoyed writing the
essays it contains. It is unlikely that they have achieved all that I set out to do. I hope
the reader will at least find some pleasure in perusing them, whatever the merits of the
text.
6
Part I

Action
Another random document with
no related content on Scribd:
Myyminen ja ostaminen on ohitse.

Kaikki aartehistot ovat kasatut kokoon molemmin puolin, ja minun


on aika mennä kotiin.

Mutta, ovenvartija, kysytkö tulliasi?

Älä pelkää, minulla on vielä jotakin jäljellä. Kohtaloni ei ole


kaikessa vetänyt nenästä minua.

Tuulen tyyneys uhkaa myrskyä, eivätkä turmiokkaat pilvet


lännessä ennusta hyvää.

Hiljainen vesi vartoo tuulispäätä.

Kiirehdin joen yli kulkemaan, ennenkuin yö minut yllättää.

Hoi, lauttamies, sinä odotat palkkaasi!

Kyllä, veljeni, minulla on vielä jotakin jäljellä. Kohtaloni ei ole


kaikessa vetänyt nenästä minua.

Tien varrella, puun varjossa, istuu kerjäläinen. Ah, hän katsoo


kasvoihini arasti toivoen!

Hän luulee, että olen rikas päivän säästöistäni.

Kyllä, veljeni, minulla on vielä jotakin jäljellä. Kohtaloni ei ole


kaikessa vetänyt nenästä minua.

Yö pimenee ja katu yksinäistyy.


Tulenkipinät hiiluvat läpi lehtien.

Ken olet sinä, joka seuraat minua hiipivin, hiljaisin askelin?

Ah, tiedän, että toivosi on ryöstää kaikki säästöni. En tahdo tuottaa


sinulle mielipahaa.

Sillä minulla on vielä jotakin jäljellä. Kohtaloni ei ole kaikessa


vetänyt nenästä minua.

Tulen kotiin keskiyöksi. Käteni ovat tyhjät.

Odotat tuskaisin silmin ovellani, vaiti ja unetonna.

Kuin uupunut lintu lennät povelleni kiihkeässä rakkaudessa.

Oi, oi Jumalani, paljon on vielä jäljellä. Kohtaloni ei ole kaikessa


vetänyt nenästä minua.

59

Et mitään loppumatonta hyvää anna, suvaitsevainen ja sumuinen


äiti, tomu!

Kulutat voimasi täyttääksesi lastesi suut, mutta ravintosi on niukka.

Ilosi lahja, jonka suot meille, ei ole koskaan täydellinen.

Leikkikalut, joita laitat lapsillesi, ovat hauraita.


Et voi täyttää kaikkia nälkäisiä toiveitamme, mutta miksi sinut sen
vuoksi hylkäisin?

Hymysi, tuskan varjostama, on suloinen nähdä silmilleni.

Rakkautesi, joka ei tunne täyttymystä, on kallis sydämelleni.

Povesi on ruokkinut meitä elämällä, mutta ei kuolemattomuudella;


siksi valvovat silmäsi ainiaan.

Aikakausia olet värein ja lauluin työskennellyt, mutta vieläkään ei


taivaasi ole valmis, ainoastaan sen heikko mielikuva.

Kyynelsumu on kauneusluomiesi yllä.

Tahdon tyhjentää lauluni mykkään sydämeesi ja lempeni sinun


lempeesi.

Tahdon turvata sinut työllä.

Olen nähnyt vienot kasvosi ja rakastan murheellista tomuasi, Äiti


Maa.

60

Maailman vastaanottosaleissa viihtyvät yksinkertaiset heinänkorret


samalla nurmikolla päivänsäteiden ja keskiyön tähtien kanssa.

Niinpä jakavat lauluni tyyssijansa maailman sydämessä pilvien ja


metsien sävelten kanssa.
Mutta, rikas mies, sinun hyvinvoinnillasi ei ole mitään osaa
auringon iloisen kullan ja mietiskelevän, kimmeltävän kuun
yksinkertaisesta suuruudesta.

Kaikkisyleilevän taivaan siunaus ei ole langennut sen yli.

Kun kuolema tulee, se kalpenee, kuihtuu ja hajoaa tomuksi.

61

Keskiyöllä sanoi askeetiksi aikovainen:

"Nyt on aikani jättää kotini ja etsiä Jumalaa. Ah, kuka on niin


kauan pitänyt minua tässä harhaluulossa?"

Jumala kuiskasi: "Minä." Mutta miehen korvat olivat suljetut.

Nukkuva lapsonen rinnoillaan makasi hänen vaimonsa


rauhallisessa levossaan vuoteen toisella puolen.

Mies sanoi: "Kuka olet sinä, joka olet minua niin kauan
hulluttanut?"

Ääni sanoi jälleen: "Jumala." Mutta mies ei kuullut sitä.

Lapsi nyyhki unissaan ja puristautui lähemmä äitiään.

Jumala käski: "Seis, hullu, älä jätä kotiasi!" Mutta mies ei kuullut
vieläkään.
Jumala huokasi valittaen: "Miksi vaeltaa palvelijani minua
etsimään ja samalla jättää minut?"

62

Oli toukokuu. Tukahduttava iltapäivä tuntui äärettömän pitkältä.


Kuiva maa ammotteli janoisena helteessään.

Silloin kuulin joelta äänen, joka sanoi: "Tule, armahaiseni!"

Suljin kirjani, avasin ikkunan ja katsoin ulos.

Näin suuren, suonvärisen puhvelin seisomassa joen rannalla


tyynine, kärsivällisille silmineen; ja nuoren puhvelin polvistuvana
vedessä ja pyytävänä sitä uimaan.

Hymyilin huvittuneena ja tunsin suloisen henkäyksen


sydämessäni.

63

Miksi kuiskit niin hiljaa korviini, oi Kuolema, minun Kuolemani?

Kun kukkaset putoavat illan suussa ja karjat palajavat


omettoihinsa, hiivit hiljaa minun vierelleni ja puhut sanoja, joita en
tajua.
Näinkö sinun täytyy etsiä ja saavuttaa minut uneliaan muminan ja
kylmien suuteloiden oopiumilla, oi Kuolema, minun Kuolemani?

Eikö häitämme seuraa mitkään komeat juhlamenot?

Etkö tahdo kiinnittää seppeltä ruskeihin, kihariin kutreihisi?

Eikö ole ketään, joka kantaisi lippua sinun edessäsi ja eikö yö ole
punaisten soihtujen loimosta valaistuva, oi Kuolema, minun
Kuolemani?

Tule rauskuvine raakunkuorinesi, tule unettomassa yössä!

Pue minut karmosiinipunaiseen vaippaan, tartu käteeni ja ota


minut!

Valmista valjakkosi kärsimättömästä tömistelevine hevosineen


oveni eteen!

Kohota huntuni Ja katso minua ylpeästi silmiin, oi Kuolema, minun


Kuolemani!

64

Tulemme leikkimään tänä yönä kuoleman leikkiä, morsiameni ja


minä.

Yö on synkkä, pilvet taivaalla oikulliset ja aallot merellä raivokkaat.


Olemme jättäneet untemme vuoteen, sysänneet auki oven ja
päässeet ulos, morsiameni ja minä.

Istumme keinussa, ja hurja myrskytuuli meitä takaa tuudittelee.

Morsiameni syöksyy ylös peläten ja riemuiten, värisee ja kietoutuu


rintapieliini.

Kauan olen häntä hellästi säilyttänyt.

Laitoin hänelle kukkaisvuoteen ja suljin ovet estääkseni kiusallisen


valon hänen silmiltään.

Suutelin häntä somasti suulle ja kuiskin armaita sanoja hänen


korviinsa, siksi kun hän puoliksi taintui raukeaan riutumukseen.

Hän on haihtunut epämääräisen sulouden pohjattomaan


terheneen.

Hän ei vastannut kosketukseeni, lauluni eivät voineet häntä


herättää.

Yöllä on myrskytuulen viesti vierinyt meille.

Morsiameni värisi ja nousi, hän tarttui käteeni ja tuli ulos.

Hänen hapsensa lentävät tuulessa, hänen huntunsa hulmuaa,


hänen kukkakiehkuransa kahisee hänen povellaan.

Kuoleman henkäys on kutsunut hänet elämään.

Me seisomme silmä silmää, sydän sydäntä vasten, morsiameni ja


minä.
65

Viheliäisten ja keltaisten riisivainioiden yli luovat syksyn varjot


pilviään, joita nopsa-askelinen päivä ajelee. Mehiläiset unohtavat
imeä hunajaansa; valon juovuttamina ne liehuvat ja surisevat kuin
hullut

Sorsat joen saarissa hälisevät ilosta tyhjän takia.

Älkää antako kenenkään palata kotiinsa tänä aamuna, veljet,


ainoankaan ei työhön!

Valloittakaamme hyökkäyksellä sininen taivas ja työstäkäämme


aarteet avaruuden!

Nauru kulkee ilmassa kuin vaahto virralla.

Veljet, tuhlatkaamme aamumme arvottomiin lauleloihin!

66

Ken olet, lukija, joka luet laulujani vuosisatoja tämän jälkeen?

En voi lähettää sinulle yksinäistä kukkaa tämän keväämme


runsaudesta, en yksinäistä kultajuovaa pilvien korkeudesta.

Avaa ovesi ja katso ympärillesi!

Kokoa tuoksuvia muistoja kukkivasta tarhastasi, vuosisatoja sitten


kuihtuneiden kukkien muistoja!
Tunteos sydämesi ilossa elävä riemu, joka lauloi eräänä kevään
aamuna kaiuttaen hilpeät sävelensä halki vuosisatojen.
*** END OF THE PROJECT GUTENBERG EBOOK PUUTARHURI
***

Updated editions will replace the previous one—the old editions will
be renamed.

Creating the works from print editions not protected by U.S.


copyright law means that no one owns a United States copyright in
these works, so the Foundation (and you!) can copy and distribute it
in the United States without permission and without paying copyright
royalties. Special rules, set forth in the General Terms of Use part of
this license, apply to copying and distributing Project Gutenberg™
electronic works to protect the PROJECT GUTENBERG™ concept
and trademark. Project Gutenberg is a registered trademark, and
may not be used if you charge for an eBook, except by following the
terms of the trademark license, including paying royalties for use of
the Project Gutenberg trademark. If you do not charge anything for
copies of this eBook, complying with the trademark license is very
easy. You may use this eBook for nearly any purpose such as
creation of derivative works, reports, performances and research.
Project Gutenberg eBooks may be modified and printed and given
away—you may do practically ANYTHING in the United States with
eBooks not protected by U.S. copyright law. Redistribution is subject
to the trademark license, especially commercial redistribution.

START: FULL LICENSE


THE FULL PROJECT GUTENBERG LICENSE
PLEASE READ THIS BEFORE YOU DISTRIBUTE OR USE THIS WORK

To protect the Project Gutenberg™ mission of promoting the free


distribution of electronic works, by using or distributing this work (or
any other work associated in any way with the phrase “Project
Gutenberg”), you agree to comply with all the terms of the Full
Project Gutenberg™ License available with this file or online at
www.gutenberg.org/license.

Section 1. General Terms of Use and


Redistributing Project Gutenberg™
electronic works
1.A. By reading or using any part of this Project Gutenberg™
electronic work, you indicate that you have read, understand, agree
to and accept all the terms of this license and intellectual property
(trademark/copyright) agreement. If you do not agree to abide by all
the terms of this agreement, you must cease using and return or
destroy all copies of Project Gutenberg™ electronic works in your
possession. If you paid a fee for obtaining a copy of or access to a
Project Gutenberg™ electronic work and you do not agree to be
bound by the terms of this agreement, you may obtain a refund from
the person or entity to whom you paid the fee as set forth in
paragraph 1.E.8.

1.B. “Project Gutenberg” is a registered trademark. It may only be


used on or associated in any way with an electronic work by people
who agree to be bound by the terms of this agreement. There are a
few things that you can do with most Project Gutenberg™ electronic
works even without complying with the full terms of this agreement.
See paragraph 1.C below. There are a lot of things you can do with
Project Gutenberg™ electronic works if you follow the terms of this
agreement and help preserve free future access to Project
Gutenberg™ electronic works. See paragraph 1.E below.
1.C. The Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation (“the
Foundation” or PGLAF), owns a compilation copyright in the
collection of Project Gutenberg™ electronic works. Nearly all the
individual works in the collection are in the public domain in the
United States. If an individual work is unprotected by copyright law in
the United States and you are located in the United States, we do
not claim a right to prevent you from copying, distributing,
performing, displaying or creating derivative works based on the
work as long as all references to Project Gutenberg are removed. Of
course, we hope that you will support the Project Gutenberg™
mission of promoting free access to electronic works by freely
sharing Project Gutenberg™ works in compliance with the terms of
this agreement for keeping the Project Gutenberg™ name
associated with the work. You can easily comply with the terms of
this agreement by keeping this work in the same format with its
attached full Project Gutenberg™ License when you share it without
charge with others.

1.D. The copyright laws of the place where you are located also
govern what you can do with this work. Copyright laws in most
countries are in a constant state of change. If you are outside the
United States, check the laws of your country in addition to the terms
of this agreement before downloading, copying, displaying,
performing, distributing or creating derivative works based on this
work or any other Project Gutenberg™ work. The Foundation makes
no representations concerning the copyright status of any work in
any country other than the United States.

1.E. Unless you have removed all references to Project Gutenberg:

1.E.1. The following sentence, with active links to, or other


immediate access to, the full Project Gutenberg™ License must
appear prominently whenever any copy of a Project Gutenberg™
work (any work on which the phrase “Project Gutenberg” appears, or
with which the phrase “Project Gutenberg” is associated) is
accessed, displayed, performed, viewed, copied or distributed:
This eBook is for the use of anyone anywhere in the United
States and most other parts of the world at no cost and with
almost no restrictions whatsoever. You may copy it, give it away
or re-use it under the terms of the Project Gutenberg License
included with this eBook or online at www.gutenberg.org. If you
are not located in the United States, you will have to check the
laws of the country where you are located before using this
eBook.

1.E.2. If an individual Project Gutenberg™ electronic work is derived


from texts not protected by U.S. copyright law (does not contain a
notice indicating that it is posted with permission of the copyright
holder), the work can be copied and distributed to anyone in the
United States without paying any fees or charges. If you are
redistributing or providing access to a work with the phrase “Project
Gutenberg” associated with or appearing on the work, you must
comply either with the requirements of paragraphs 1.E.1 through
1.E.7 or obtain permission for the use of the work and the Project
Gutenberg™ trademark as set forth in paragraphs 1.E.8 or 1.E.9.

1.E.3. If an individual Project Gutenberg™ electronic work is posted


with the permission of the copyright holder, your use and distribution
must comply with both paragraphs 1.E.1 through 1.E.7 and any
additional terms imposed by the copyright holder. Additional terms
will be linked to the Project Gutenberg™ License for all works posted
with the permission of the copyright holder found at the beginning of
this work.

1.E.4. Do not unlink or detach or remove the full Project


Gutenberg™ License terms from this work, or any files containing a
part of this work or any other work associated with Project
Gutenberg™.

1.E.5. Do not copy, display, perform, distribute or redistribute this


electronic work, or any part of this electronic work, without
prominently displaying the sentence set forth in paragraph 1.E.1 with
active links or immediate access to the full terms of the Project
Gutenberg™ License.
1.E.6. You may convert to and distribute this work in any binary,
compressed, marked up, nonproprietary or proprietary form,
including any word processing or hypertext form. However, if you
provide access to or distribute copies of a Project Gutenberg™ work
in a format other than “Plain Vanilla ASCII” or other format used in
the official version posted on the official Project Gutenberg™ website
(www.gutenberg.org), you must, at no additional cost, fee or expense
to the user, provide a copy, a means of exporting a copy, or a means
of obtaining a copy upon request, of the work in its original “Plain
Vanilla ASCII” or other form. Any alternate format must include the
full Project Gutenberg™ License as specified in paragraph 1.E.1.

1.E.7. Do not charge a fee for access to, viewing, displaying,


performing, copying or distributing any Project Gutenberg™ works
unless you comply with paragraph 1.E.8 or 1.E.9.

1.E.8. You may charge a reasonable fee for copies of or providing


access to or distributing Project Gutenberg™ electronic works
provided that:

• You pay a royalty fee of 20% of the gross profits you derive from
the use of Project Gutenberg™ works calculated using the
method you already use to calculate your applicable taxes. The
fee is owed to the owner of the Project Gutenberg™ trademark,
but he has agreed to donate royalties under this paragraph to
the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation. Royalty
payments must be paid within 60 days following each date on
which you prepare (or are legally required to prepare) your
periodic tax returns. Royalty payments should be clearly marked
as such and sent to the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive
Foundation at the address specified in Section 4, “Information
about donations to the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive
Foundation.”

• You provide a full refund of any money paid by a user who


notifies you in writing (or by e-mail) within 30 days of receipt that
s/he does not agree to the terms of the full Project Gutenberg™
License. You must require such a user to return or destroy all
copies of the works possessed in a physical medium and
discontinue all use of and all access to other copies of Project
Gutenberg™ works.

• You provide, in accordance with paragraph 1.F.3, a full refund of


any money paid for a work or a replacement copy, if a defect in
the electronic work is discovered and reported to you within 90
days of receipt of the work.

• You comply with all other terms of this agreement for free
distribution of Project Gutenberg™ works.

1.E.9. If you wish to charge a fee or distribute a Project Gutenberg™


electronic work or group of works on different terms than are set
forth in this agreement, you must obtain permission in writing from
the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation, the manager of
the Project Gutenberg™ trademark. Contact the Foundation as set
forth in Section 3 below.

1.F.

1.F.1. Project Gutenberg volunteers and employees expend


considerable effort to identify, do copyright research on, transcribe
and proofread works not protected by U.S. copyright law in creating
the Project Gutenberg™ collection. Despite these efforts, Project
Gutenberg™ electronic works, and the medium on which they may
be stored, may contain “Defects,” such as, but not limited to,
incomplete, inaccurate or corrupt data, transcription errors, a
copyright or other intellectual property infringement, a defective or
damaged disk or other medium, a computer virus, or computer
codes that damage or cannot be read by your equipment.

1.F.2. LIMITED WARRANTY, DISCLAIMER OF DAMAGES - Except


for the “Right of Replacement or Refund” described in paragraph
1.F.3, the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation, the owner
of the Project Gutenberg™ trademark, and any other party
distributing a Project Gutenberg™ electronic work under this
agreement, disclaim all liability to you for damages, costs and
expenses, including legal fees. YOU AGREE THAT YOU HAVE NO
REMEDIES FOR NEGLIGENCE, STRICT LIABILITY, BREACH OF
WARRANTY OR BREACH OF CONTRACT EXCEPT THOSE
PROVIDED IN PARAGRAPH 1.F.3. YOU AGREE THAT THE
FOUNDATION, THE TRADEMARK OWNER, AND ANY
DISTRIBUTOR UNDER THIS AGREEMENT WILL NOT BE LIABLE
TO YOU FOR ACTUAL, DIRECT, INDIRECT, CONSEQUENTIAL,
PUNITIVE OR INCIDENTAL DAMAGES EVEN IF YOU GIVE
NOTICE OF THE POSSIBILITY OF SUCH DAMAGE.

1.F.3. LIMITED RIGHT OF REPLACEMENT OR REFUND - If you


discover a defect in this electronic work within 90 days of receiving it,
you can receive a refund of the money (if any) you paid for it by
sending a written explanation to the person you received the work
from. If you received the work on a physical medium, you must
return the medium with your written explanation. The person or entity
that provided you with the defective work may elect to provide a
replacement copy in lieu of a refund. If you received the work
electronically, the person or entity providing it to you may choose to
give you a second opportunity to receive the work electronically in
lieu of a refund. If the second copy is also defective, you may
demand a refund in writing without further opportunities to fix the
problem.

1.F.4. Except for the limited right of replacement or refund set forth in
paragraph 1.F.3, this work is provided to you ‘AS-IS’, WITH NO
OTHER WARRANTIES OF ANY KIND, EXPRESS OR IMPLIED,
INCLUDING BUT NOT LIMITED TO WARRANTIES OF
MERCHANTABILITY OR FITNESS FOR ANY PURPOSE.

1.F.5. Some states do not allow disclaimers of certain implied


warranties or the exclusion or limitation of certain types of damages.
If any disclaimer or limitation set forth in this agreement violates the
law of the state applicable to this agreement, the agreement shall be
interpreted to make the maximum disclaimer or limitation permitted
by the applicable state law. The invalidity or unenforceability of any
provision of this agreement shall not void the remaining provisions.

1.F.6. INDEMNITY - You agree to indemnify and hold the


Foundation, the trademark owner, any agent or employee of the
Foundation, anyone providing copies of Project Gutenberg™
electronic works in accordance with this agreement, and any
volunteers associated with the production, promotion and distribution
of Project Gutenberg™ electronic works, harmless from all liability,
costs and expenses, including legal fees, that arise directly or
indirectly from any of the following which you do or cause to occur:
(a) distribution of this or any Project Gutenberg™ work, (b)
alteration, modification, or additions or deletions to any Project
Gutenberg™ work, and (c) any Defect you cause.

Section 2. Information about the Mission of


Project Gutenberg™
Project Gutenberg™ is synonymous with the free distribution of
electronic works in formats readable by the widest variety of
computers including obsolete, old, middle-aged and new computers.
It exists because of the efforts of hundreds of volunteers and
donations from people in all walks of life.

Volunteers and financial support to provide volunteers with the


assistance they need are critical to reaching Project Gutenberg™’s
goals and ensuring that the Project Gutenberg™ collection will
remain freely available for generations to come. In 2001, the Project
Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation was created to provide a
secure and permanent future for Project Gutenberg™ and future
generations. To learn more about the Project Gutenberg Literary
Archive Foundation and how your efforts and donations can help,
see Sections 3 and 4 and the Foundation information page at
www.gutenberg.org.
Section 3. Information about the Project
Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation
The Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation is a non-profit
501(c)(3) educational corporation organized under the laws of the
state of Mississippi and granted tax exempt status by the Internal
Revenue Service. The Foundation’s EIN or federal tax identification
number is 64-6221541. Contributions to the Project Gutenberg
Literary Archive Foundation are tax deductible to the full extent
permitted by U.S. federal laws and your state’s laws.

The Foundation’s business office is located at 809 North 1500 West,


Salt Lake City, UT 84116, (801) 596-1887. Email contact links and up
to date contact information can be found at the Foundation’s website
and official page at www.gutenberg.org/contact

Section 4. Information about Donations to


the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive
Foundation
Project Gutenberg™ depends upon and cannot survive without
widespread public support and donations to carry out its mission of
increasing the number of public domain and licensed works that can
be freely distributed in machine-readable form accessible by the
widest array of equipment including outdated equipment. Many small
donations ($1 to $5,000) are particularly important to maintaining tax
exempt status with the IRS.

The Foundation is committed to complying with the laws regulating


charities and charitable donations in all 50 states of the United
States. Compliance requirements are not uniform and it takes a
considerable effort, much paperwork and many fees to meet and
keep up with these requirements. We do not solicit donations in
locations where we have not received written confirmation of
compliance. To SEND DONATIONS or determine the status of
compliance for any particular state visit www.gutenberg.org/donate.

While we cannot and do not solicit contributions from states where


we have not met the solicitation requirements, we know of no
prohibition against accepting unsolicited donations from donors in
such states who approach us with offers to donate.

International donations are gratefully accepted, but we cannot make


any statements concerning tax treatment of donations received from
outside the United States. U.S. laws alone swamp our small staff.

Please check the Project Gutenberg web pages for current donation
methods and addresses. Donations are accepted in a number of
other ways including checks, online payments and credit card
donations. To donate, please visit: www.gutenberg.org/donate.

Section 5. General Information About Project


Gutenberg™ electronic works
Professor Michael S. Hart was the originator of the Project
Gutenberg™ concept of a library of electronic works that could be
freely shared with anyone. For forty years, he produced and
distributed Project Gutenberg™ eBooks with only a loose network of
volunteer support.

Project Gutenberg™ eBooks are often created from several printed


editions, all of which are confirmed as not protected by copyright in
the U.S. unless a copyright notice is included. Thus, we do not
necessarily keep eBooks in compliance with any particular paper
edition.

Most people start at our website which has the main PG search
facility: www.gutenberg.org.

This website includes information about Project Gutenberg™,


including how to make donations to the Project Gutenberg Literary

You might also like