Full download Leibniz on the Problem of Evil Paul Rateau file pdf all chapter on 2024

You might also like

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 31

Leibniz on the Problem of Evil Paul

Rateau
Visit to download the full and correct content document:
https://ebookmass.com/product/leibniz-on-the-problem-of-evil-paul-rateau/
More products digital (pdf, epub, mobi) instant
download maybe you interests ...

The Problem of Evil: Eight Views in Dialogue N N


Trakakis

https://ebookmass.com/product/the-problem-of-evil-eight-views-in-
dialogue-n-n-trakakis/

John Chrysostom on Paul: Praises and Problem Passages


Margaret M. Mitchell

https://ebookmass.com/product/john-chrysostom-on-paul-praises-
and-problem-passages-margaret-m-mitchell/

Leibniz: General Inquiries on the Analysis of Notions


and Truths Massimo Mugnai

https://ebookmass.com/product/leibniz-general-inquiries-on-the-
analysis-of-notions-and-truths-massimo-mugnai/

The Philosophical Roots of Loneliness and Intimacy:


Political Narcissism and the Problem of Evil 1st ed.
2022 Edition Mijuskovic

https://ebookmass.com/product/the-philosophical-roots-of-
loneliness-and-intimacy-political-narcissism-and-the-problem-of-
evil-1st-ed-2022-edition-mijuskovic/
Leibniz on Time, Space, and Relativity Richard T. W.
Arthur

https://ebookmass.com/product/leibniz-on-time-space-and-
relativity-richard-t-w-arthur/

Leibniz on Time, Space, and Relativity Richard T. W.


Arthur

https://ebookmass.com/product/leibniz-on-time-space-and-
relativity-richard-t-w-arthur-2/

Kant on Evil, Self-Deception, and Moral Reform Laura


Papish

https://ebookmass.com/product/kant-on-evil-self-deception-and-
moral-reform-laura-papish/

Evil in Mind: The Psychology of Harming Others


Christopher T. Burris

https://ebookmass.com/product/evil-in-mind-the-psychology-of-
harming-others-christopher-t-burris/

The Leibniz-Caroline-Clarke Correspondence Gregory


Brown

https://ebookmass.com/product/the-leibniz-caroline-clarke-
correspondence-gregory-brown/
Leibniz on the Problem of Evil
Leibniz on the Problem
of Evil
Paul Rateau

1
1
Oxford University Press is a department of the University of Oxford. It furthers
the University’s objective of excellence in research, scholarship, and education
by publishing worldwide. Oxford is a registered trade mark of Oxford University
Press in the UK and certain other countries.

Published in the United States of America by Oxford University Press


198 Madison Avenue, New York, NY 10016, United States of America.

© Oxford University Press 2019

All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in


a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, without the
prior permission in writing of Oxford University Press, or as expressly permitted
by law, by license, or under terms agreed with the appropriate reproduction
rights organization. Inquiries concerning reproduction outside the scope of the
above should be sent to the Rights Department, Oxford University Press, at the
address above.

You must not circulate this work in any other form


and you must impose this same condition on any acquirer.

Library of Congress Cataloging- in- Publication Data


Names: Rateau, Paul, author.
Title: Leibniz on the problem of evil / Paul Rateau.
Other titles: Question du mal chez Leibniz. English
Description: New York : Oxford University Press, 2019. |
Includes bibliographical references and index.
Identifiers: LCCN 2018050787 (print) | LCCN 2019011220 (ebook) |
ISBN 9780199996513 (updf) | ISBN 9780199350971 (online content) |
ISBN 9780190054564 (epub) | ISBN 9780199996506 (cloth : alk. paper)
Subjects: LCSH: Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm, Freiherr von, 1646-1716. Essais
de th?eodic?ee. | Theodicy. | Good and evil. | Free will and determinism.
Classification: LCC B2590 .Z7 (ebook) | LCC B2590 .Z7 R3813 2019 (print) |
DDC 231/.8—dc23
LC record available at https://lccn.loc.gov/2018050787

1 3 5 7 9 8 6 4 2

Printed by Sheridan Books, Inc., United States of America


CON T E N T S

Acknowledgments  vii
List of Abbreviations   ix

Introduction  1
1. The Existence of Evil   1
2. Evil Considered in Relation to Justice   5
3. A Vocation: To Defend God’s Justice   10
1. Difficulties Concerning the Justification of God in the Years
Prior to 1673  18
1.1. Early Reading and the Relation of Justice to Power   18
1.2. A Just God, Who Is Nevertheless The Author of Sin?   32
2. The Confession of a Philosopher: Divine Justice and the Necessity
of Sin  54
2.1. God as Ground, but Not Author of Evil   54
2.2. Permission of Evil and the Distinction of Two Kinds of
Necessity: A Limited Rehabilitation   66
3. Theoretical Changes After the Confession of a Philosopher: Toward
a New Conception of God, the Possible, and Divine Concurrence
with Evil  88
3.1. A Revised Theology and Metaphysics   89
3.2. The Origin of Evil and God’s Physical Concurrence   108
3.3. God’s Moral Concurrence with Evil and the Relation of
Part to Whole  119
4. The Genesis of Theodicy: Its Scientific and Apologetic Aims   142
4.1. From the Project of “Theodicies” to the Composition of the Essays
of Theodicy: Systematic Necessity and Occasional Cause   143
4.2. Theodicy as Defense: Ignorance of Detail, Presumptions,
and Probabilities  160
5. The Best of All Possible Worlds and Divine Permission of Evil   183
5.1. The Thesis of the Best of All Possible Worlds   184

(v)
( vi ) Contents

5.2. The Moral Necessity of the Divine Choice   200


5.3. God’s Moral Concurrence with Evil: The Doctrine of
Permission  216
6. Evil in Being and in the Actions of Creatures: Reality or
Appearance?  241
6.1. God’s Physical Concurrence, the Origin and Nature of Evil   241
6.2. The Inertial Model and Its Application to Creaturely Actions:
From Peccability to Malice   258
6.3. Real Defect or False Appearance: A Dual Conception of
Evil  276
7. Human Freedom and Principles of Action   300
7.1. The Labyrinth of the Free and the Necessary and the Prerequisites
of Freedom   302
7.2. From the Ideal to the Real: The Exercise of Freedom and the
Maxims of Leibnizian Ethics   323
Conclusion  345

Bibliography  351
Index  359
AC K N O W L E D GM E N T S

I would like to express my deep gratitude to Todd Ryan for his very careful
translation, helpful advice, and comments. This work would not have been
possible without his continuing commitment and friendly support.
I would also like to thank Mark Kulstad who first had the idea for this
project and Samuel Newlands who warmly welcomed and supported it.
Finally, I am grateful to the John Templeton Foundation who generously
granted their financial support.

( vii )
A B B R EV I AT ION S

ABBREVIATIONS FOR LEIBNIZ’S WORKS

A Leibniz: Sämtliche Schriften und Briefe. Edited by Prussian


Academy, then Berlin-​Brandenburg Academy, and Academy
of Göttingen. Darmstadt, then Leipzig and Berlin, 1923–​.
Cited by series, volume, and page number.
AG Philosophical Essays. Translated by Roger Ariew and Daniel
Garber. Indianapolis: Hackett, 1989.
C Opuscules et fragments inédits de Leibniz. Extraits des
manuscrits de la bibliothèque de Hanovre. Edited by Louis
Couturat. Paris: Alcan, 1903; repr. Hildesheim: Georg
Olms, 1966.
Causa Dei Causa Dei asserta per Justitiam ejus, cum caeteris ejus
Perfectionibus, cunctisque Actionibus conciliatam. Cited by
section number.
CP Confessio Philosophi (The Confession of a Philosopher).
DM Discourse on Metaphysics. Cited by section number.
Dutens G. G. Leibnitii Opera omnia, Nunc primum collecta. In Classes
distributa, praefationibus et indicibus exornata, studio
L. Dutens. 6 vols. Geneva: 1768; repr. Hildesheim: Georg
Olms, 1990.
FC (L) Lettres et Opuscules inédits de Leibniz. Introduction by
Louis-​Alexandre Foucher de Careil. Paris: Ladrange, 1854;
repr. Hildesheim: Georg Olms, 1975.
FC (NL) Nouvelles lettres et opuscules inédits de Leibniz. Introduction
by Louis-​Alexandre Foucher de Careil. Paris: Durand, 1857;
repr. Hildesheim: Georg Olms, 1971.
FC (O) Œuvres de Leibniz, publiées pour la première fois d’après
les manuscrits originaux. Notes and introduction by

( ix )
(x) List of Abbreviations

Louis-​Alexandre Foucher de Careil. 7 vols. Paris: Didot,


1859–​1875; repr. Hildesheim: Georg Olms, 1969.
GB Briefwechsel zwischen Leibniz und Christian Wolff. Aus den
Handschriften der Königlichen Bibliothek zu Hannover. Edited
by C. I. Gerhardt. Halle: 1860; repr. Hildesheim: Georg
Olms, 1971.
GM Leibnizens mathematische Schriften. Edited by C. I.
Gerhardt. 7 vols. Berlin then Halle: 1849–​1863; repr.
Hildesheim: Georg Olms, 1962. Cited by volume and page
number.
GP Die philosophischen Schriften von Leibniz. Edited
by C. I. Gerhardt. 7 vols. Berlin 1875–​1890; repr.
Hildesheim: Georg Olms, 1960–​1961. Cited by volume and
page number.
Grua Leibniz. Textes inédits d’après les manuscrits de la Bibliothèque
provinciale de Hanovre, ed. and notes by Gaston Grua.
2 vols. Paris: PUF, 1948.
Guhrauer Leibniz’s Deutsche Schriften. Edited by G. E. Guhrauer.
2 vols. Berlin, 1838–​1840.
Huggard Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz. Theodicy. Essays on the Goodness
of God, the Freedom of Man and the Origin of Evil. Edited and
with an introduction by Austin Farrer. Translated by E. M.
Huggard. New Haven: Yale University Press, 1952.
Klopp Die Werke von Leibniz gemäss seinem handschriftlichen
Nachlasse in der Königlichen Bibliothek zu Hannover. Edited
by O. Klopp. Series I. 11 vols. Hanover, 1864–​1884.
L G. W. Leibniz. Philosophical Papers and Letters. Edited
and translated by Leroy E. Loemker. Dordrecht: Reidel,
1969.
LR The Leibniz-​Des Bosses Correspondence. Edited and
translated by Brandon C. Look and Donald Rutherford.
New Haven: Yale University Press, 2007.
Mollat Mittheilungen aus Leibnizens ungedruckten Schriften. Edited
by Georg Mollat. Kassel, 1887; repr. Leipzig, 1893.
NE New Essays on Human Understanding. Cited by book,
chapter, and section number.
Pk De Summa Rerum: Metaphysical Papers, 1675–​1676. Edited
and translated by G. H. R. Parkinson. New Haven: Yale
University Press, 1992.
PNG The Principles of Nature and of Grace, Based on Reason. Cited
by section number.
List of Abbreviations ( xi )

R The Political Writings of Leibniz. Edited and translated


by Patrick Riley. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 1972.
RB New Essays on Human Understanding. Translated
by Peter Remnant and Jonathan Francis Bennett.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996.
S Monadology and Other Philosophical Essays. Gottfried
Wilhelm von Leibniz. Translated by Paul and Anne
Martin Schrecker. With an Introduction and Notes
by Paul Schrecker. Indianapolis, New York, Kansas
City: Bobbs-​Merrill, 1965.
Sleigh G. W. Leibniz. Confessio Philosophi. Papers Concerning the
Problem of Evil, 1671–​1678. Edited, translated, and with
an introduction by Robert C. Sleigh, Jr. New Haven and
London: Yale University Press, 2005.
SLT The Shorter Leibniz Texts: A Collection of New
Translations. Edited and translated by Lloyd Strickland.
London: Continuum, 2006.
T Theodicy: Essays on the Goodness of God, the Freedom of Man
and the Origin of Evil. Cited by section number.
T ob Observations on the Book Concerning the Origin of Evil
Published Recently in England. Cited by section number.
T pd Preliminary Discourse on the Conformity of Faith with Reason.
Cited by section number.
T ref Reflections on the Work Published by M. Hobbes in English on
Freedom, Necessity and Chance. Cited by section number.
Ts Summary of the Controversy reduced to Formal Arguments.

ABBREVIATIONS FOR OTHER PRIMARY SOURCES


Aquinas

ST Summa Theologica. Translated by Fathers of the English


Dominican Province. New York: Benzinger Brothers, 1947.

Bayle

OD Œuvres Diverses de Mr. Pierre Bayle. 4 vols. The


Hague: 1727–​1761; repr. Hildesheim: Georg Olms,
1964–​1982.
( xii ) List of Abbreviations

Descartes

AT Œuvres de Descartes. Edited by Charles Adam and


Paul Tannery, 11 vols. (plus a vol. including biography
and supplement). Paris: L. Cerf, 1897–​1913. New
edition: Paris: Vrin/​CNRS, 1964–​1974.
CSM The Philosophical Writings of Descartes. Edited and
translated by John Cottingham, Robert Stoothoff, and
Dugald Murdoch. 2 vols. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 1985.
CSMK The Philosophical Writings of Descartes. Volume 3: The
Correspondence. Translated and edited by John
Cottingham, Robert Stoothoff, Dugald Murdoch, and
Anthony Kenny. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 1991.

Hobbes

EW The English Works of Thomas Hobbes of Malmesbury. Edited


by William Molesworth. 11 vols. London: Bohn, Longman,
Brown, Green, and Longmans, 1839–​1845.

Luther

WA D. Martin Luthers Werke: Kritische Gesamtausgabe [Weimarer


Ausgabe]. 120 vols. Weimar: H. Böhlau and H. Böhlaus
Nachfolger, 1883–​2009.
Leibniz on the Problem of Evil
Introduction

1. THE EXISTENCE OF EVIL

Let it be said from the outset: for Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz (1646–​1716),
evil is not an enigma or an “unparalleled challenge” threatening to put an
end to philosophy and rational theology. Far from posing an unsolvable
theoretical problem,1 evil does not defy rational investigation. Nor does
this examination lead to the denial of the reality of evil in the world—​al-
though Leibniz refuses to exaggerate its extent, with the result that he has
sometimes appeared to commentators as lacking a “dramatic sense of sin”2
and as shrugging off the “tragedy of human existence.”3 On the contrary,
for Leibniz, the fact of evil is undeniable:

[O]‌ne cannot deny that there is in the world physical evil (that is, suffering) and
moral evil (that is, crime) and even that physical evil is not always distributed
here on earth according to the proportion of moral evil, as it seems that justice
demands.4

Evil is not a mere appearance that results from our partial under-
standing of things and vanishes altogether when we regard the universe
from the correct point of view. Although, metaphysically speaking, evil is
merely a privation, it is not a pure nothing, but that which limits perfection
and being and so resists and impedes the good. The forms that evil takes
(flaws, disorders, natural calamities, monsters, errors, ignorance, sin, vice
and pain) are as varied as the good it limits, even if it is reduced at Theodicy
§21 to three fundamental kinds (metaphysical, physical, and moral evil).

(1)
(2) Leibniz on the Problem of Evil

Leibniz neither questions nor seeks to minimize either the effects them-
selves or their pervasiveness—​ indeed, prosperity—​ in the world. In
thinking about evil, Leibniz does not ignore experience, even if he refutes
objections against providence based solely on its evidence.
Leibniz is not unaware of the evils and misfortunes of his time. On the
contrary, his philosophical investigation is undertaken from a practical
perspective. As Donald Rutherford has convincingly argued,5 Leibniz’s
Theodicy and metaphysics are indissolubly linked to moral concerns and
are wholly oriented toward the improvement of the human condition
through the exercise of reason. However, his goal is not exclusively moral
in the strict sense of the term, for it is also, more broadly, political and re-
ligious. In keeping with his well-​known motto, Theoria cum praxi (“Theory
with Practice”), Leibniz’s philosophical reflection on evil is accompanied by
a constant and relentless struggle against the concrete forms in which evil
appears in the world. The various undertakings and projects he pursued
during the course of his life—​however various and disparate they may
appear—​were all born of a desire to work for the perfection and happi-
ness of human beings, including at the material level, by relieving their
misery. These efforts included attempts at reunification of the churches
(both among the Protestant churches and with Rome); scientific projects
(an encyclopedia of human knowledge, plans for the foundation of
academies and learned societies); mathematical and technical inventions;
support for the arts and literature; research relating to demographics and
the economy (especially the idea of founding insurance funds and creating
public storehouses permanently stocked with primary goods); proposals
to reform the law and contemporary judicial procedures; and political and
diplomatic missions. All of these projects and undertakings illustrate his
firm conviction that intellectual activity ought not to be separated from ac-
tion and “engagement” in the world in the service of neighbor and society.
The just man must consider everything he does and everything for which
he labors from the perspective of the “general good” and the glory of God.
Leibniz well understood the contemporary situation in Germany, which
had been exhausted by the Thirty Years’ War (1618–​1648). He describes
the suffering of this war, which saw German princes tear each other apart,
and whose effects continued to be felt long after the signing of the Treaty
of Westphalia.6 In various pamphlets and manifestos, Leibniz took excep-
tion to the expansionist politics of France and denounced the disastrous
consequences of the wars instigated by Louis XIV.7 In a letter to Marshal
Villars (May 1704), Leibniz expresses outrage at the terrible repression
of the Protestants of Cevennes carried out by Villars under orders from
Louis XIV and accuses Villars of becoming “the infamous minister of his
Introduction (3)

[the king’s] fury and the cruel executioner of his innocent compatriots.”8
When reading these pages in which Leibniz vigorously denounces the
injustices committed by France in Europe, and the inhumanity, cruelty,
and barbarism of Marshal Villars, one can almost wonder whether this is
the same man who defends the existence of the best of all possible worlds!
André Robinet has rightly wondered, “What is the meaning of the Theodicy,
if Leibniz was so familiar with the existence of real and concrete evil?”9
Is there a gap between Leibniz the metaphysician and Leibniz the pam-
phleteer and politician? The thesis of the best of all possible worlds does
not imply the perfection of every one of its parts. In no way is this thesis
the result of blindness, ignorance, or indifference to worldly affairs. It
does not amount to a legitimization of the present state of things on the
grounds that they cannot fail to be good, since they belong to the best of all
possible worlds. Nor should it lead to resignation or inaction. On the con-
trary, the task of the just man is to work tirelessly for the good, despite all
obstacles and setbacks, and to make the future better to the utmost of his
ability by altering those things that need reform.
Thus, Leibniz is perfectly aware of the weight of evil in the world and
of its consequences at every level: moral, religious (confessional divisions,
intolerance), social, economic (poverty, famine), and political (war and
its attendant evils). For Leibniz, the sole source of evil is man. For this
reason, “it is only the will that men lack to deliver themselves from an in-
finity of evils.”10 Indeed, the will of some few would often suffice to bring
relief to entire nations. Man is “one of the most powerful creatures and
one of the most capable of causing evil.” The faculty of reason with which
he is endowed makes him capable of causing much evil, for which reason
“one single Caligula, one Nero, has caused more evil than an earthquake.
An evil man takes pleasure in causing suffering and destruction, for which
there are only too many opportunities.”11 Here, forty-​five years prior to the
Lisbon earthquake (1755), is Leibniz’s response to those who would accuse
God of all the disorders of the world: no natural evil can compare to what
human beings do and are capable of doing to one another.
Must we then conclude that Leibniz held a rather dim view of human
beings and that behind his metaphysical “optimism” lies a certain anthro-
pological “pessimism”? Certain texts can give this impression.12 However,
Leibniz generally avoids excessively dramatizing evil and exaggerating
human misery in the manner of Augustine, Luther, or Pascal. For Leibniz,
even if human beings cannot be saved without Christ, it does not follow
that pagan virtue is a false virtue and that of necessity all of their actions
are sinful.13 Leibniz has little regard for those authors who take pleasure
in portraying humans as wicked and contemptible, hypocritical and
(4) Leibniz on the Problem of Evil

deceitful.14 By emphasizing evil, such accounts only add to it and lead us to


believe that it generally predominates over the good. For Leibniz, it is un-
just to degrade the human condition in this way. It is even sinful to portray
human beings as so evil and contemptible, since it is a failure to recognize
the goodness that God has shown us.15 In fact,

this [moral] evil is not even so great in men as it is declared to be. It is only
people of a malicious disposition or those who have become somewhat misan-
thropic through misfortunes, like Lucian’s Timon, who find wickedness eve-
rywhere, and who poison the best actions by the interpretations they give to
them.16

The disposition to “make an evil of everything” is fundamentally harmful


to society and serves to teach human beings to be wicked.17 Furthermore,
Leibniz is wary of those who speak of the evils and faults of humans
“without the slightest intention of taking effective measures to remedy
them,” and who prefer instead to waste their time “in impotent wishes and
useless complaints.”18
Evil exists. However, our tendency is to exaggerate it. This explains the
success of those who would portray human nature as depraved and the
world as full of evil. In reality, human beings pay greater attention to evil
than to good and, as a consequence, are more inclined to believe that on
balance the evil of the universe outweighs the good both in quantity and
intensity. Like health, the good often goes unrecognized. It is less notice-
able and frequently passes unobserved, whereas evil is exaggerated.

It is only want of attention that diminishes our good, and this attention must be
given to us through some admixture of evils. If we were usually sick and seldom
in good health, we should be wonderfully sensible of that great good and we
should be less sensible of our evils. But is it not better, notwithstanding, that
health should be usual and sickness the exception?19

Thus, our sense that evils are greater and more numerous than goods does
not prove that they really are so. On the contrary, it shows that they are
not, since we notice only what is rare and pay no attention to the ordinary
and habitual: “evil arouses our attention rather than good: but this same
reason proves that evil is more rare.”20
Paradoxically, the tendency to exaggerate evil can be found among
theologians as well as skeptics and atheists—​although for exactly opposite
reasons. Evil serves as an argument for apologists as well as critics. In the
case of the former, the omnipresence of evil in the world shows the need
Introduction (5)

for a redeemer, the Christ. In the case of the latter, it calls into question
either the existence of God or his unity and consequently his power (ac-
cording to the Manichean hypothesis popularized by Pierre Bayle) or his
justice. Leibniz seems to adopt a more measured approach. He does not
dismiss the experience of evil; however, he treats it with caution in light of
our natural tendency to exaggerate it. For Leibniz, evil cannot serve as the
basis for a serious objection to the existence of God or to monotheism. On
the other hand, it unquestionably poses a problem with regard to justice,
which is an attribute traditionally ascribed to God. It is for this reason that
a doctrine of God’s justice, that is, a théo-​dicée in the literal sense of the
term, is necessary.21 It is within the framework of this doctrine that the
theoretical difficulties raised by the existence of evil can be resolved.

2. EVIL CONSIDERED IN RELATION TO JUSTICE

The manner in which Leibniz approaches the problem of evil is original in


that it is explicitly connected with the theme of justice.22 The first question
raised by evil is not “Why does it exist?” or the traditional “Where does it
come from?” (Unde malum?), but rather “Who is responsible for it?” The
issue is, in the first instance, moral and juridical because it is the ques-
tion of imputation that is at stake. Obviously, the metaphysical aspects and
implications of the problem are not overlooked, but they are considered
only subsequently, when the inquiry turns to the origin of evil and its es-
sence. Why does Leibniz adopt this juridical approach? As is well known,
Leibniz was a jurist. In the preface of the Theodicy, he takes on the role of
a lawyer who pleads the cause of God.23 As we shall see, Leibniz appeals in
the defensive wing of the Theodicy to the rules of controversy that he set
out in the Preliminary Discourse24 and that are clearly inspired by judicial
debates.
However, I believe that Leibniz adopts a juridical point of view for a more
fundamental reason: he considers injustice to be the true evil. Injustice is
all that violates the law (natural or positive): injustice committed (sin) as
well as injustice suffered (undeserved physical pain and moral grief). For
Leibniz, evil is not a scandal in and of itself. It becomes shocking when it
seems to be unjustly distributed, when pain befalls one who did not de-
serve it, when sin is not followed by any punishment and even proves prof-
itable to the sinner. The existence of suffering, misfortune, calamity, and
the fact that there are wicked people in the world would not be so prob-
lematic if this suffering as well as these misfortunes and calamities only
happened to the wicked. In this case, evil would be easily justified, since it
Another random document with
no related content on Scribd:
about donations to the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive
Foundation.”

• You provide a full refund of any money paid by a user who


notifies you in writing (or by e-mail) within 30 days of receipt that
s/he does not agree to the terms of the full Project Gutenberg™
License. You must require such a user to return or destroy all
copies of the works possessed in a physical medium and
discontinue all use of and all access to other copies of Project
Gutenberg™ works.

• You provide, in accordance with paragraph 1.F.3, a full refund of


any money paid for a work or a replacement copy, if a defect in
the electronic work is discovered and reported to you within 90
days of receipt of the work.

• You comply with all other terms of this agreement for free
distribution of Project Gutenberg™ works.

1.E.9. If you wish to charge a fee or distribute a Project


Gutenberg™ electronic work or group of works on different
terms than are set forth in this agreement, you must obtain
permission in writing from the Project Gutenberg Literary
Archive Foundation, the manager of the Project Gutenberg™
trademark. Contact the Foundation as set forth in Section 3
below.

1.F.

1.F.1. Project Gutenberg volunteers and employees expend


considerable effort to identify, do copyright research on,
transcribe and proofread works not protected by U.S. copyright
law in creating the Project Gutenberg™ collection. Despite
these efforts, Project Gutenberg™ electronic works, and the
medium on which they may be stored, may contain “Defects,”
such as, but not limited to, incomplete, inaccurate or corrupt
data, transcription errors, a copyright or other intellectual
property infringement, a defective or damaged disk or other
medium, a computer virus, or computer codes that damage or
cannot be read by your equipment.

1.F.2. LIMITED WARRANTY, DISCLAIMER OF DAMAGES -


Except for the “Right of Replacement or Refund” described in
paragraph 1.F.3, the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive
Foundation, the owner of the Project Gutenberg™ trademark,
and any other party distributing a Project Gutenberg™ electronic
work under this agreement, disclaim all liability to you for
damages, costs and expenses, including legal fees. YOU
AGREE THAT YOU HAVE NO REMEDIES FOR NEGLIGENCE,
STRICT LIABILITY, BREACH OF WARRANTY OR BREACH
OF CONTRACT EXCEPT THOSE PROVIDED IN PARAGRAPH
1.F.3. YOU AGREE THAT THE FOUNDATION, THE
TRADEMARK OWNER, AND ANY DISTRIBUTOR UNDER
THIS AGREEMENT WILL NOT BE LIABLE TO YOU FOR
ACTUAL, DIRECT, INDIRECT, CONSEQUENTIAL, PUNITIVE
OR INCIDENTAL DAMAGES EVEN IF YOU GIVE NOTICE OF
THE POSSIBILITY OF SUCH DAMAGE.

1.F.3. LIMITED RIGHT OF REPLACEMENT OR REFUND - If


you discover a defect in this electronic work within 90 days of
receiving it, you can receive a refund of the money (if any) you
paid for it by sending a written explanation to the person you
received the work from. If you received the work on a physical
medium, you must return the medium with your written
explanation. The person or entity that provided you with the
defective work may elect to provide a replacement copy in lieu
of a refund. If you received the work electronically, the person or
entity providing it to you may choose to give you a second
opportunity to receive the work electronically in lieu of a refund.
If the second copy is also defective, you may demand a refund
in writing without further opportunities to fix the problem.

1.F.4. Except for the limited right of replacement or refund set


forth in paragraph 1.F.3, this work is provided to you ‘AS-IS’,
WITH NO OTHER WARRANTIES OF ANY KIND, EXPRESS
OR IMPLIED, INCLUDING BUT NOT LIMITED TO
WARRANTIES OF MERCHANTABILITY OR FITNESS FOR
ANY PURPOSE.

1.F.5. Some states do not allow disclaimers of certain implied


warranties or the exclusion or limitation of certain types of
damages. If any disclaimer or limitation set forth in this
agreement violates the law of the state applicable to this
agreement, the agreement shall be interpreted to make the
maximum disclaimer or limitation permitted by the applicable
state law. The invalidity or unenforceability of any provision of
this agreement shall not void the remaining provisions.

1.F.6. INDEMNITY - You agree to indemnify and hold the


Foundation, the trademark owner, any agent or employee of the
Foundation, anyone providing copies of Project Gutenberg™
electronic works in accordance with this agreement, and any
volunteers associated with the production, promotion and
distribution of Project Gutenberg™ electronic works, harmless
from all liability, costs and expenses, including legal fees, that
arise directly or indirectly from any of the following which you do
or cause to occur: (a) distribution of this or any Project
Gutenberg™ work, (b) alteration, modification, or additions or
deletions to any Project Gutenberg™ work, and (c) any Defect
you cause.

Section 2. Information about the Mission of


Project Gutenberg™
Project Gutenberg™ is synonymous with the free distribution of
electronic works in formats readable by the widest variety of
computers including obsolete, old, middle-aged and new
computers. It exists because of the efforts of hundreds of
volunteers and donations from people in all walks of life.

Volunteers and financial support to provide volunteers with the


assistance they need are critical to reaching Project
Gutenberg™’s goals and ensuring that the Project Gutenberg™
collection will remain freely available for generations to come. In
2001, the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation was
created to provide a secure and permanent future for Project
Gutenberg™ and future generations. To learn more about the
Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation and how your
efforts and donations can help, see Sections 3 and 4 and the
Foundation information page at www.gutenberg.org.

Section 3. Information about the Project


Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation
The Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation is a non-
profit 501(c)(3) educational corporation organized under the
laws of the state of Mississippi and granted tax exempt status by
the Internal Revenue Service. The Foundation’s EIN or federal
tax identification number is 64-6221541. Contributions to the
Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation are tax
deductible to the full extent permitted by U.S. federal laws and
your state’s laws.

The Foundation’s business office is located at 809 North 1500


West, Salt Lake City, UT 84116, (801) 596-1887. Email contact
links and up to date contact information can be found at the
Foundation’s website and official page at
www.gutenberg.org/contact

Section 4. Information about Donations to


the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive
Foundation
Project Gutenberg™ depends upon and cannot survive without
widespread public support and donations to carry out its mission
of increasing the number of public domain and licensed works
that can be freely distributed in machine-readable form
accessible by the widest array of equipment including outdated
equipment. Many small donations ($1 to $5,000) are particularly
important to maintaining tax exempt status with the IRS.

The Foundation is committed to complying with the laws


regulating charities and charitable donations in all 50 states of
the United States. Compliance requirements are not uniform
and it takes a considerable effort, much paperwork and many
fees to meet and keep up with these requirements. We do not
solicit donations in locations where we have not received written
confirmation of compliance. To SEND DONATIONS or
determine the status of compliance for any particular state visit
www.gutenberg.org/donate.

While we cannot and do not solicit contributions from states


where we have not met the solicitation requirements, we know
of no prohibition against accepting unsolicited donations from
donors in such states who approach us with offers to donate.

International donations are gratefully accepted, but we cannot


make any statements concerning tax treatment of donations
received from outside the United States. U.S. laws alone swamp
our small staff.

Please check the Project Gutenberg web pages for current


donation methods and addresses. Donations are accepted in a
number of other ways including checks, online payments and
credit card donations. To donate, please visit:
www.gutenberg.org/donate.

Section 5. General Information About Project


Gutenberg™ electronic works
Professor Michael S. Hart was the originator of the Project
Gutenberg™ concept of a library of electronic works that could
be freely shared with anyone. For forty years, he produced and
distributed Project Gutenberg™ eBooks with only a loose
network of volunteer support.

Project Gutenberg™ eBooks are often created from several


printed editions, all of which are confirmed as not protected by
copyright in the U.S. unless a copyright notice is included. Thus,
we do not necessarily keep eBooks in compliance with any
particular paper edition.

Most people start at our website which has the main PG search
facility: www.gutenberg.org.

This website includes information about Project Gutenberg™,


including how to make donations to the Project Gutenberg
Literary Archive Foundation, how to help produce our new
eBooks, and how to subscribe to our email newsletter to hear
about new eBooks.
back

You might also like