Full download Rousseau's God. Theology, Religion, and the Natural Goodness of Man 1st Edition John T. Scott file pdf all chapter on 2024

You might also like

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 37

Rousseau's God.

Theology, Religion,
and the Natural Goodness of Man 1st
Edition John T. Scott
Visit to download the full and correct content document:
https://ebookmass.com/product/rousseaus-god-theology-religion-and-the-natural-goo
dness-of-man-1st-edition-john-t-scott/
More products digital (pdf, epub, mobi) instant
download maybe you interests ...

Rousseau's God John T. Scott

https://ebookmass.com/product/rousseaus-god-john-t-scott/

The Grace of Being Fallible in Philosophy, Theology,


and Religion 1st ed. Edition Thomas John Hastings

https://ebookmass.com/product/the-grace-of-being-fallible-in-
philosophy-theology-and-religion-1st-ed-edition-thomas-john-
hastings/

Reflections on God and the Death of God: Philosophy,


Spirituality, and Religion Richard White

https://ebookmass.com/product/reflections-on-god-and-the-death-
of-god-philosophy-spirituality-and-religion-richard-white/

Trinitarian Theology in Medieval and Reformation


Thought 1st ed. Edition John T. Slotemaker

https://ebookmass.com/product/trinitarian-theology-in-medieval-
and-reformation-thought-1st-ed-edition-john-t-slotemaker/
Analytic Theology and the Academic Study of Religion
William Wood

https://ebookmass.com/product/analytic-theology-and-the-academic-
study-of-religion-william-wood/

The Awe of God John Bevere

https://ebookmass.com/product/the-awe-of-god-john-bevere/

God, Knowledge, and the Good: Collected Papers in the


Philosophy of Religion Linda Trinkaus Zagzebski

https://ebookmass.com/product/god-knowledge-and-the-good-
collected-papers-in-the-philosophy-of-religion-linda-trinkaus-
zagzebski/

John Webster: The Shape and Development of His


Theology: The Shape and Development of His Theology
Jordan Senner

https://ebookmass.com/product/john-webster-the-shape-and-
development-of-his-theology-the-shape-and-development-of-his-
theology-jordan-senner/

Living Religion: Embodiment, Theology, and the


Possibility of a Spiritual Sense James W. Jones

https://ebookmass.com/product/living-religion-embodiment-
theology-and-the-possibility-of-a-spiritual-sense-james-w-jones/
Rousseau’s God
Rousseau’s God
T h e ol o g y, R e l ig ion,
a n d t h e N at u r a l G o odn e s s
of M a n

John T. Scott

The University of Chicago Press Chicago and London


The University of Chicago Press, Chicago 60637
The University of Chicago Press, Ltd., London
© 2023 by The University of Chicago
All rights reserved. No part of this book may be used or reproduced in any manner
whatsoever without written permission, except in the case of brief quotations
in critical articles and reviews. For more information, contact the University of
Chicago Press, 1427 E. 60th St., Chicago, IL 60637.
Published 2023
Printed in the United States of America

32 31 30 29 28 27 26 25 24 23 1 2 3 4 5

ISBN-13: 978-0-226-82548-9 (cloth)


ISBN-13: 978-0-226-82550-2 (paper)
ISBN-13: 978-0-226-82549-6 (e-book)
DOI: https://doi.org/10.7208/chicago/9780226825496.001.0001

Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data

Names: Scott, John T., 1963– author.


Title: Rousseau’s God : theology, religion, and the natural goodness of man /
John T. Scott.
Description: Chicago ; London : The University of Chicago Press, 2023. |
Includes bibliographical references and index.
Identifiers: LCCN 2022035681 | ISBN 9780226825489 (cloth) | ISBN 9780226825502
(paperback) | ISBN 9780226825496 (ebook)
Subjects: LCSH: Rousseau, Jean-Jacques, 1712–1778—Religion. | Theology. |
Religion. | Philosophical anthropology. | Philosophy and religion.
Classification: LCC B2138.R4 S46 2023 | DDC 220.6—dc23/eng/20220909
LC record available at https://lccn.loc.gov/2022035681

This paper meets the requirements of ANSI/NISO Z39.48-1992


(Permanence of Paper).
For Adrienne
Con t en ts

List of Abbreviations ix

Introduction 1

Chapter 1
T r u t h a n d U t i l i t y 20
Chapter 2
The Theodicy of the
D i s c o u r s e o n I n e q u a l i t y 56
Chapter 3
Pride and Providence in the
L e t t e r t o V o lta i r e 85
Chapter 4
Psychic Unit y and Disunit y and
t h e N e e d f o r R e l i g i o n 108
Chapter 5
Introduction to the
“ P r o f e s s i o n o f Fa i t h ” 131
Chapter 6
The Theological Teaching of the
“ P r o f e s s i o n o f Fa i t h ” 149
Chapter 7
T h e C r i t i q u e — a n d R e v i va l — o f
R e l i g i o n i n t h e “ P r o f e s s i o n o f Fa i t h ” 188
Chapter 8
O n C i v i l R e l i g i o n 201
C o n c l u s i o n 229

Acknowledgments 233
Notes 235
Bibliography 251
Index 259
A bbr e v i at ions

For those writings by Rousseau on which I focus, I use the abbreviated


titles and do so parenthetically within the text. For other writings by
Rousseau, I use an abbreviated title and identify the edition from which
the work is drawn. All translations from primary and secondary sources
are my own unless otherwise noted. I sometimes alter translations with-
out so noting, using the Pléiade edition of the Oeuvres complètes unless
otherwise noted.

CC Correspondence complète. Ed. Ralph A. Leigh. 50 vols. Oxford:


Voltaire Foundation, 1965–91.
CW The Collected Writings of Rousseau. Ed. Roger D. Masters and
Christopher Kelly. 13 vols. Hanover: University Press of New
England, 1990–2010.
OC Oeuvres complètes. 5 vols. Bibliothèque de la Pléiade. Paris:
Gallimard, 1959–95.

Beaumont Letter to Beaumont. In CW, vol. 9.


Contract On the Social Contract; or, Principles of Political Right. In The
Major Political Writings of Jean-Jacques Rousseau, trans. and
ed. John T. Scott. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2012.
Emile Emile, or On Education. Trans. Allan Bloom. New York: Basic
Books, 1979.
Inequality Discourse on the Origin and Foundations of Inequality among
Men. In The Major Political Writings of Jean-Jacques Rousseau,
trans. and ed. John T. Scott. Chicago: University of Chicago
Press, 2012.
Mountain Letters Written from the Mountain. In CW, vol. 9.
Reveries Reveries of the Solitary Walker. In CW, vol. 11.
x L i s t of A b b r e v i a t io n s

Sciences Discourse on the Sciences and the Arts. In The Major Political
Writings of Jean-Jacques Rousseau, trans. and ed. John T. Scott.
Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2012.
Voltaire Letter to Voltaire. In CW, vol. 3.
Introduction

On the evening of June 8, 1762, Rousseau learned that an order for his
arrest had been issued. His recently published work, Emile, or On Educa-
tion, had been condemned by the Parliament of Paris, in large part for
the discussion of theology and religion contained in the separate section
of the work titled the “Profession of Faith of the Savoyard Vicar.” The
author was then living in Montmorency, about ten miles north of Paris,
having retreated from the city to the countryside six years earlier to em-
bark on a personal reformation. His friends and sometime hosts there,
the duc and duchesse de Luxembourg, and other supporters gathered in
the night to confer and counseled him to flee to England. “Jean-Jacques
does not know how to hide,” he declared. Nonetheless, the next morning
Jean-Jacques fled. But he did not hide. After breakfasting, he climbed
into a borrowed cabriolet, insisting that the folding top remain down.
As he left the grounds of the estate, he passed the carriage carrying the
officials arriving to arrest him. Readily recognizable in his Armenian
costume of a caftan and tall fur hat, Rousseau defiantly drove straight
through Paris and then headed east toward his native Geneva. Ten days
later his fellow citizens condemned Emile, along with the Social Contract
for good measure, burning the offending books and ordering his arrest.
After canvassing his options, the fugitive headed on foot for the tiny
village of Môtiers, nestled in the mountains above Lake Neuchâtel.1 A
month later he learned that a pastoral letter had been issued by Chris-
tophe de Beaumont, archbishop of Paris, censuring Emile. Rousseau had
accomplished something of a trifecta of persecuted authors of the eigh-
teenth century, earning the wrath of secular and religious authorities,
Catholics and Protestants alike, with his controversial writings.
In his open reply to the archbishop of Paris, the Letter to Beaumont,
Rousseau defended the publication of Emile, and especially the “Profes-
2 I n t r odu c t io n

sion of Faith.” He explained the philosophical system of which Emile was


an expression. “The fundamental principle of all morality about which
I have reasoned in all my writings and developed in this last one with
all the clarity of which I was capable is that man is a naturally good be-
ing, loving justice and order; that there is no original perversity in the
human heart, and that the first movements of nature are always right”
(Beaumont, 28; see also Letters to Malesherbes, CW, 5:575; Dialogues, CW,
1:22–23, 209–13).2 The corollary to the natural goodness of man is his
corruption in society. Rousseau therefore claims that he has been able
to explain the source of our wickedness without resorting to the doc-
trine of original sin, admitting to the archbishop that his philosophical
system is directed against that gloomy doctrine. “Original sin explains
everything except its own principle, and it is this principle that has to be
explained. . . . Man was created good. We both agree on that, I believe.
But you say he is wicked because he was wicked. And I show how he was
wicked. Which of us, in your opinion, better ascends to the principle?”
(Beaumont, 31). As for the “Profession of Faith,” he makes an astonishing
declaration: “I will always consider it the best and most useful writing
in the century during which I published it” (46–47). His phraseology
here—that he “published” the “Profession of Faith” as opposed to ac-
knowledging that he wrote it—indicates the problematic relationship
between the “Profession of Faith” and the text of Emile, and indeed
Rousseau’s entire corpus.
Why did Rousseau publish the “Profession of Faith,” indeed publish
it at such considerable personal risk to himself? How are the theological
and religious teachings promulgated by the Savoyard Vicar related to
Rousseau’s philosophical system of the natural goodness of man? What
does Rousseau argue in his own name concerning theological and reli-
gious issues? The questions raised by Rousseau’s defense of Emile and
the “Profession of Faith” are the subject of this book.
Rousseau’s God offers a comprehensive interpretation of Rousseau’s
theological and religious writings, both in themselves and in relation to
his philosophy and political theory as a whole. The themes of theology
and religion run throughout Rousseau’s writings. In the prize essay that
began his career as the most famous writer of the time, the Discourse on
the Sciences and the Arts (1751), one of the central complaints against
the deleterious moral effects of the sciences and the arts was how they
undermined healthy religious sentiments. “But those vain and futile de-
claimers go about everywhere, armed with their deadly paradoxes, un-
dermining the foundations of faith and annihilating virtue. They laugh
disdainfully at those old-fashioned words ‘fatherland’ and ‘religion’ and
I n t r o du c t i o n 3

consecrate their talents and their philosophy to destroying and degrad-


ing all that is sacred among men” (Sciences, 25). In the Discourse on In-
equality (1755) Rousseau proclaims the central tenet of his philosophi-
cal system, the natural goodness of man, and claims that this doctrine
serves to “justify nature,” making the work a theodicy or physiodicy.
He made the intention of his second Discourse manifest in his Letter to
Voltaire (1756), directed against Voltaire’s “Poem on the Lisbon Earth-
quake,” where he defended the natural goodness of man and of nature
itself. Rousseau turned more overtly to theological and religious themes
in Emile (1762), with its lengthy “Profession of Faith,” and the Social
Contract (1762), the longest chapter of which is “On Civil Religion.” He
defended the content of the theological and religious thought expressed
in these writings and explained his intentions in publishing them in the
Letter to Beaumont (1763) and Letters Written from the Mountain (1764).
Finally, the questions of God and providence, fate and hope, preoccupy
Rousseau in his last, autobiographical writings.
When I speak of Rousseau’s theological and religious thought I differ-
entiate between these two related subjects as theory is related to practice.
That is, theology is a branch of philosophy devoted to reasoning about
God, providence, and so on, whereas religion concerns the beliefs, doc-
trines, and practices involved in the worship of the divinity. Rousseau
writes on both subjects, sometimes separately and sometimes together.
Most notably, this division structures the two parts of the “Profession
of Faith.” The first part contains the Vicar’s theological reasonings based
on his understanding of nature and human nature, of the existence and
nature of the divinity, and of the human soul, freedom, and conscience
in relation to the divinity. The second part is devoted to a critique of reli-
gious beliefs and practices such as revelation, miracles, and scripture. By
contrast, whereas the “Profession of Faith” contains an extensive discus-
sion of theology, the chapter “On Civil Religion” in the Social Contract
limits itself to a single sentence on the positive doctrines necessary for
a civil religion and instead focuses on the utility (or lack thereof) of re-
ligious beliefs and practices from the perspective of politics. Since one
of Rousseau’s main strategies across his writings is to limit theological
doctrines to a minimum so as to maximize potential assent to them, and
this in order to make them practically efficacious, his theological and
religious views cannot be entirely separated.
The overall argument of my inquiry is that there is a complicated
relationship between Rousseau’s philosophy of the natural goodness of
man, on the one hand, and his theological and religious thought, on the
other, which revolves around what can be framed as two oppositions:
4 I n t r odu c t io n

first, between the attributes or needs of natural man and social or moral
man; second, between the criteria of truth and utility.
As for the first opposition, I argue that Rousseau’s solution to the
problem of evil and therewith his justification of God and nature ex-
tends only to natural man, that is, humans considered as physical beings
existing under the physical laws of nature, such as he portrays human
nature in the pure state of nature. I later add a caveat to this argument
by examining how in Emile Rousseau takes up the task of educating a
developed social or moral being in such a way as to maintain his natu-
ral goodness and psychic unity, if on another plane than that of natural
man, and thereby extend his theodicy and physiodicy beyond physical
man simplicitur. Yet this justification is insufficient for social man as he
ordinarily develops in society, that is, from the perspective of developed
humans who, in part owing to amour-propre, demand justification and
consolation for the internal divisions they experience and the injustices
they believe they suffer. Rousseau must therefore supplement the natu-
ral or physical providence that applies to physical man with a teaching
concerning divine particular providence required by social or moral man,
even though that teaching is at best doubtful in his view. This leads to
the second set of oppositions.
Rousseau argues that theological and religious doctrines must be
assessed by two criteria, truth and utility, criteria that he importantly
also insists cannot be assumed to be consistent with one another. The
theological and religious views he expresses throughout his writings,
whether in his own name or in the voice of the Savoyard Vicar or oth-
ers, are offered by him as less true than useful. They are presented as true
up to a point and with an eye to the limits of human knowledge, but
beyond that point as beliefs or opinions that fulfill our psychological
need for hope and consolation. They are advanced as useful in various
ways depending on the context: psychologically, morally, or politically.
In sum, I therefore see a consistency of substance and aim across his
theological and religious writings both in themselves and in relation to
his philosophy. Let me clarify that I am not arguing that the theologi-
cal and religious views he advances are “merely” useful, and that in two
respects. First, they are not “merely” useful, because under certain as-
sumptions they may also be true. For example, if Rousseau is a deist
who believes in the divinity, such a belief would from his perspective be
both true and useful. Second, whatever their truth value, they are not
“merely” useful in the sense of manipulative or simply instrumental, but
are instead intended to be salutary with regard to human virtue and hap-
piness, or one might say “truly” salutary.
I n t r o du c t i o n 5

The Natural Goodness of Man and the Problem of Religion


Rousseau famously proclaims that a single principle unifies all of his
works and comprises a “system”: the natural goodness of man. But no
less important for understanding his philosophy, and especially his theo-
logical and religious writings, is the corollary of his “great principle”:
society makes men wicked. The juxtaposition of our natural goodness
and current wickedness is clear in Rousseau’s first assertion of his prin-
ciple, in the Discourse on Inequality: “Men are wicked; sad and continual
experience spares the need for proof. Yet man is naturally good—I do
believe I have demonstrated it” (Inequality, note IX, 127). Indeed, in
my own view, the power of Rousseau’s writings is most fully felt in his
diagnosis of the evils we experience in ourselves and in our relations
with others. He gives full-throated and eloquent voice to the corrupt-
ing effects of personal dependence, the psychic disunity we experience
as we are torn between our inclinations and duties, the perils of feeling
our existence through the opinions of others, the false veils of polite-
ness and civility with which we are swathed, the pains of unrequited
love and disappointing friendships, and so on.3 The psychic disunity
and the evils experienced by developed humans are what, according to
Rousseau, lead them to turn to religion to explain their predicament and
to offer consolation and hope. Or so I will argue.
Locating Rousseau within the seventeenth- and eighteenth-century
debates over theology and especially the problem of evil, and the schol-
arly literature on them, helps bring out what is important and perhaps
unique about his theological and religious writings. Since my business
here is not to canvass these debates, my attention to this issue will neces-
sarily be brief. Fortunately, others have gone before me.
Particularly helpful is how Ernst Cassirer situates Rousseau within
Enlightenment debates over the problem of evil. According to Cassirer,
most Enlightenment thinkers, and particularly French thinkers includ-
ing Voltaire and the Encyclopedists, held a critical and skeptical attitude
toward religion, or at least toward superstition and religious authorities,
a stance captured by Voltaire’s battle cry, Écrasez l’infâme! In turn, they
tended to embrace or at least proclaim their allegiance to a deism that
led to a rather optimistic or even casual attitude toward the problem of
evil, whether on the level of the cosmos or the individual. Such thinkers
include Locke, Shaftesbury, Toland, and Leibniz, and the English among
them especially influenced the French thinkers of the eighteenth cen-
tury. According to Cassirer, and other scholars as well, it was the Lisbon
earthquake of All Saints’ Day 1715 that shook Voltaire, usually so urbane
6 I n t r odu c t io n

and insouciant about the problem of evil, with his optimism tumbling
down along with that of many of his fellow travelers.4 The intellectual
aftershocks of the Lisbon earthquake may be overstated, but it is an apt
place to dwell, since I devote a chapter of this book to Rousseau’s Letter
to Voltaire and their engagement over the problem of evil. The paradox of
Rousseau’s reply to Voltaire’s “Poem on the Lisbon Earthquake” is that
he defends a form of optimism against what he sees as Voltaire’s pessi-
mistic indictment of providence, while at the same time acknowledging
that the evils we suffer as human beings are all too real. This paradoxi-
cal combination of optimism and realism, not to say pessimism, runs
through Rousseau’s exposition of the system of the natural goodness of
man and his corruption in society throughout his writings.
Once again, Cassirer is helpful on this issue. When he turns in his
survey of the problem of evil in the Enlightenment to the “thoroughly
original trend of thought” seen in Rousseau, Cassirer repeats what he
has written in his study devoted to Rousseau’s thought concerning his
novel solution to the problem of evil—namely, by locating the source of
evil in society and thus in men themselves,5 an interpretation I take up
in chapter 2. But he also offers another helpful lens through which we
can see Rousseau’s unique place in seventeenth- and eighteenth-century
thought. Cassirer says of Rousseau: “He is the first thinker in the eigh-
teenth century to take Pascal’s accusation against men seriously and to
feel its full force. Instead of softening it, instead of attributing it to the
self-torturing mood of a brooding misanthropist, as Voltaire had done,
Rousseau grasps its cardinal point.”6 Once again, this gets to the heart
of Rousseau’s thought: while he agrees with Pascal about the psychic
division, misery, and evil we experience, he denies the sublime misan-
thrope’s argument that this evil lies in original sin, and in fact proclaims
the natural goodness of man against what he will call that “gloomy doc-
trine” (Beaumont, 31).
Pascal is probably best located in the Augustinian tradition, so cast-
ing our eyes back to the bishop of Hippo will help situate Rousseau. In
book VIII of his Confessions, where he recounts the critical moment of
his conversion, Augustine relates how he was listening to man telling of
how he, too, struggled to understand the Scriptures and to abandon his
wicked ways. “But while he was speaking, O Lord,” he says, “you were
turning me around to look at myself. For I had placed myself behind my
back, refusing to see myself. You were setting me before my own eyes so
that I could see how sordid I was . . . but there was no place where I could
escape from myself.” He summarizes the condition of his soul: “My in-
ner self was a house divided against itself.” Augustine, needless to say,
traces the source of this division to original sin. Finally, shortly afterward
I n t r o du c t i o n 7

comes the conversion scene when he hears a little girl repeating, “‘Take
it up and read, take it up and read,’” and picks up the Gospels to read: “If
you wish to be perfect, go, sell your possessions, and give the money to
the poor, and you will have treasure in heaven; then come, follow me”
(Matthew 19:21 [NRSV]).7 And so was he converted. Of course, Rous-
seau, too, wrote his own Confessions. I note that book VIII of the work
is the occasion for him to tell a story parallel to Augustine’s conversion
narrative: a story of reading a very different text, the announcement of
the prize essay competition by the Academy of Dijon in the Mercure,
which marked his own conversion in the “Illumination of Vincennes” in
which he glimpsed the principle of the natural goodness of man and his
corruption in society (Confessions, CW, 5:294–95). In short, Rousseau
turns Augustine on his head.8
As for Pascal, he is eloquent on our house being divided against itself.
To take one example among many: “Be aware, proud men, what a para-
dox you are to yourselves. Humble yourself, powerless reason! Be silent,
foolish nature! Learn that humanity infinitely transcends humanity and
hear from your Master your true condition of which you are unaware. . . .
It is astonishing however that the mystery furthest from our understand-
ing is the transmission of sin, the one thing without which we can have
no understanding of ourselves.”9 Rousseau admits the effect, that our
psychic division make us a paradox to ourselves, but denies the cause,
original sin.
For Rousseau, or so I shall argue, the doctrine of the natural good-
ness of man does not suffice for developed human beings, at least only
with rare exceptions. Proclaiming to divided and wicked beings that
they are naturally good and unified offers little consolation, especially
if the potential remedies for our condition are as difficult and as fragile
as they seem to be. Rousseau therefore turns to salutary theological and
religious teachings to offer consolation and hope to the virtuous and
a check on the wicked. The question of to what extent these teachings
cohere with his philosophy of the natural goodness of man, that is, the
extent to which Rousseau holds them to be true as well as useful, is, of
course, the subject of this study. For the present, I limit myself to sug-
gesting that the tensions between his philosophy and these theological
and religious teachings explain certain inconsistencies or even contra-
dictions other interpreters have found in his thought.
The question of the unity of Rousseau’s thought has long been an
issue faced by interpreters. For the most part, the question has revolved
around the consistency of his various writings—for example, the sup-
posed individualism of the Discourse on Inequality as opposed to the
alleged collectivism of the Social Contract. Most of these debates have
8 I n t r odu c t io n

largely been settled or rendered stale over the past fifty years and more.
What questions remain largely open concern the metaphysical and epis-
temological basis of Rousseau’s thought, including with regard to his
philosophical and theological writings, but also with regard to such is-
sues as the status of the general will.10 I restrict myself to the metaphysi-
cal and epistemological issues.
A number of interpreters have been struck by the inconsistency be-
tween what they see as the philosophical commitments of the Discourse
on Inequality and his earlier writings in general and those of his later
writings, principally Emile and the “Profession of Faith” in particular.
On the one hand, they argue that the Discourse is naturalistic, monist,
or even materialist in its basis, while Emile and the “Profession” are dual-
ist.11 Or, as one scholar has framed the issue, Rousseau seems to move
from an early Epicureanism to a later Stoicism in his thought.12 Often
what is at issue in this debate, even if the participants in the debate do
not acknowledge it, is the question of whether the views concerning
metaphysical dualism, freedom, conscience, and the like, expressed by
the Savoyard Vicar in the “Profession,” represent Rousseau’s own views
on these matters. Of course, this is one of the main subjects of the pres-
ent study. By distinguishing what the Vicar says about these matters
from Rousseau’s own stated views, I find that Rousseau is consistent
across his writings about the metaphysical and epistemological basis of
his thought.
Let me conclude this review of Rousseau’s complex position within
seventeenth- and eighteenth-century philosophical and theological
debates with what a recent and influential scholar of Enlightenment
thought has to say about Rousseau. Jonathan Israel finds Rousseau dif-
ficult to fit into his rubric of the radical versus moderate Enlightenment.
Part of his difficulty lies in squaring the deism, the immortality of the
soul, and so on, expressed by the Savoyard Vicar, which he takes with-
out comment to be Rousseau’s own views, with other elements of his
thought. He therefore speaks of Rousseau’s “hybrid status as a political
thinker who combined elements of radicalism with the moderate En-
lightenment, or rather Spinoza with Locke.”13 Indeed, Rousseau seems
to haunt Israel, who concludes his Radical Enlightenment by writing:
“What is especially remarkable about Rousseau’s thought is its Janus-
headed mixing of elements from both radical and mainstream Enlight-
enment.”14 We can all agree, I think, that Rousseau’s thought is, if any-
thing else, complex.
I n t r o du c t i o n 9

Truth and Method


Here I offer some remarks on the interpretive commitments that guide
my study and differentiate it from other treatments of the subject. What
many studies of Rousseau’s theological and religious teaching have in
common is the assumption that he is expressing his own sincere views,
whether in his own authorial voice or through the “mouthpiece” of the
Savoyard Vicar in the “Profession” or Julie in the New Heloise. In con-
trast, I do not assume that the views he expresses in his writings are
necessarily the same as his own. Indeed, I suggest that it is something of
a fool’s errand to attempt to uncover his sincere religious beliefs. I will
explain my reasons for taking this approach below. Frankly, I do not find
the question of Rousseau’s own beliefs, whatever they may be, a produc-
tive one for understanding the substance and aim of his thought. Rather,
I am concerned with what he has to say about theological and religious
subjects in his writings, what aims he has as an author in addressing
these subjects, and how what he says on these subjects helps us better
understand his philosophy as a whole.
Admittedly, Rousseau makes it tempting to assume that the theo-
logical and religious views he expresses in his own name or otherwise,
indeed the views he proclaims on any subject, are truly and sincerely his
own. Central to his authorial persona is the stance of someone reveal-
ing the truth hidden from our eyes by the false appearances of society
and the machinations of those in power. “Where could the painter and
apologist of nature, so disfigured and calumnied now, have found his
model if not in his own heart?” (Dialogues, CW, 1:214). Voltaire was
fond of comparing Jean-Jacques to Diogenes, barking from his barrel,
but Rousseau might have embraced the comparison by taking up the
lantern in search of a man only to find that he and he alone, in fact, was
that man. He adopted as his motto Vitam impendere vero—“To conse-
crate one’s life to the truth”—and throughout his writings he insisted on
his truthfulness and especially his sincerity. Finally, he upped the ante
in his autobiographical writings. How could anyone who revealed he
enjoyed being spanked, stole ribbons, exposed himself to young women,
and abandoned his children not be telling the truth?
Many readers have taken Rousseau’s authorial persona to be the man
himself. There are various versions of this approach. Among the most
influential and insightful is Jean Starobinski’s interpretation of Rousseau
as someone seeking to recapture a “transparency” lost among the “ob-
stacles” that prevent us from seeing or communicating it. Starobinski’s
psychoanalytically informed reading attends to “the emotional sources
and unconscious underpinnings of his thought,” especially as expressed
Another random document with
no related content on Scribd:
15. RUPERT GODWIN.
16. RUN TO EARTH.
17. DEAD SEA FRUIT.
18. RALPH THE BAILIFF.
19. FENTON'S QUEST.
20. LOVELS OF ARDEN.
21. ROBERT AINSLEIGH.
22. TO THE BITTER END.
23. MILLY DARRELL.
24. STRANGERS AND PILGRIMS.
25. LUCIUS DAVOREN.
26. TAKEN AT THE FLOOD.
27. LOST FOR LOVE.
28. A STRANGE WORLD.
29. HOSTAGES TO FORTUNE.
30. DEAD MEN'S SHOES.
31. JOSHUA HAGGARD.
32. WEAVERS AND WEFT.
33. AN OPEN VERDICT.
34. VIXEN.
35. THE CLOVEN FOOT.
36. THE STORY OF BARBARA.
37. JUST AS I AM.
38. ASPHODEL.
39. MOUNT ROYAL.
40. THE GOLDEN CALF.
41. PHANTOM FORTUNE.
42. FLOWER AND WEED.
43. ISHMAEL.
44. WYLLARD'S WEIRD.
45. UNDER THE RED FLAG.
46. ONE THING NEEDFUL.
47. MOHAWKS.
48. LIKE AND UNLIKE.
49. THE FATAL THREE.
50. THE DAY WILL COME.
51. ONE LIFE, ONE LOVE.
52. GERARD.
53. THE VENETIANS.
54. ALL ALONG THE RIVER.
55. THOU ART THE MAN.
56. SONS OF FIRE.
AND
57. ROUGH JUSTICE (Just Issued).

The World says:—"'Rough Justice,' one of the best of Miss


Braddon's later novels, is now included in the publisher's small,
pretty, and cheap edition of her works. The book is admirably
printed, easy to hold, and very smart in its red and gold binding."
The Daily News says:—"The book is an astonishing example of
Miss Braddon's sustained powers, of her inventiveness, her
vigour of style, and the humaneness of her character-drawing."
The Daily Chronicle says:—"This, perhaps, is the most daring
thing Miss Braddon has written."

ALSO READY, A CHEAP EDITION OF


LONDON PRIDE. Cloth, 2s. 6d.
UNDER LOVE'S RULE. 6s.
THE CHRISTMAS HIRELINGS. 3s. 6d.
Profusely illustrated.
LONDON:
SIMPKIN, MARSHALL, HAMILTON, KENT & CO., Ltd.
*** END OF THE PROJECT GUTENBERG EBOOK HIS DARLING
SIN ***

Updated editions will replace the previous one—the old editions will
be renamed.

Creating the works from print editions not protected by U.S.


copyright law means that no one owns a United States copyright in
these works, so the Foundation (and you!) can copy and distribute it
in the United States without permission and without paying copyright
royalties. Special rules, set forth in the General Terms of Use part of
this license, apply to copying and distributing Project Gutenberg™
electronic works to protect the PROJECT GUTENBERG™ concept
and trademark. Project Gutenberg is a registered trademark, and
may not be used if you charge for an eBook, except by following the
terms of the trademark license, including paying royalties for use of
the Project Gutenberg trademark. If you do not charge anything for
copies of this eBook, complying with the trademark license is very
easy. You may use this eBook for nearly any purpose such as
creation of derivative works, reports, performances and research.
Project Gutenberg eBooks may be modified and printed and given
away—you may do practically ANYTHING in the United States with
eBooks not protected by U.S. copyright law. Redistribution is subject
to the trademark license, especially commercial redistribution.

START: FULL LICENSE


THE FULL PROJECT GUTENBERG LICENSE
PLEASE READ THIS BEFORE YOU DISTRIBUTE OR USE THIS WORK

To protect the Project Gutenberg™ mission of promoting the free


distribution of electronic works, by using or distributing this work (or
any other work associated in any way with the phrase “Project
Gutenberg”), you agree to comply with all the terms of the Full
Project Gutenberg™ License available with this file or online at
www.gutenberg.org/license.

Section 1. General Terms of Use and


Redistributing Project Gutenberg™
electronic works
1.A. By reading or using any part of this Project Gutenberg™
electronic work, you indicate that you have read, understand, agree
to and accept all the terms of this license and intellectual property
(trademark/copyright) agreement. If you do not agree to abide by all
the terms of this agreement, you must cease using and return or
destroy all copies of Project Gutenberg™ electronic works in your
possession. If you paid a fee for obtaining a copy of or access to a
Project Gutenberg™ electronic work and you do not agree to be
bound by the terms of this agreement, you may obtain a refund from
the person or entity to whom you paid the fee as set forth in
paragraph 1.E.8.

1.B. “Project Gutenberg” is a registered trademark. It may only be


used on or associated in any way with an electronic work by people
who agree to be bound by the terms of this agreement. There are a
few things that you can do with most Project Gutenberg™ electronic
works even without complying with the full terms of this agreement.
See paragraph 1.C below. There are a lot of things you can do with
Project Gutenberg™ electronic works if you follow the terms of this
agreement and help preserve free future access to Project
Gutenberg™ electronic works. See paragraph 1.E below.
1.C. The Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation (“the
Foundation” or PGLAF), owns a compilation copyright in the
collection of Project Gutenberg™ electronic works. Nearly all the
individual works in the collection are in the public domain in the
United States. If an individual work is unprotected by copyright law in
the United States and you are located in the United States, we do
not claim a right to prevent you from copying, distributing,
performing, displaying or creating derivative works based on the
work as long as all references to Project Gutenberg are removed. Of
course, we hope that you will support the Project Gutenberg™
mission of promoting free access to electronic works by freely
sharing Project Gutenberg™ works in compliance with the terms of
this agreement for keeping the Project Gutenberg™ name
associated with the work. You can easily comply with the terms of
this agreement by keeping this work in the same format with its
attached full Project Gutenberg™ License when you share it without
charge with others.

1.D. The copyright laws of the place where you are located also
govern what you can do with this work. Copyright laws in most
countries are in a constant state of change. If you are outside the
United States, check the laws of your country in addition to the terms
of this agreement before downloading, copying, displaying,
performing, distributing or creating derivative works based on this
work or any other Project Gutenberg™ work. The Foundation makes
no representations concerning the copyright status of any work in
any country other than the United States.

1.E. Unless you have removed all references to Project Gutenberg:

1.E.1. The following sentence, with active links to, or other


immediate access to, the full Project Gutenberg™ License must
appear prominently whenever any copy of a Project Gutenberg™
work (any work on which the phrase “Project Gutenberg” appears, or
with which the phrase “Project Gutenberg” is associated) is
accessed, displayed, performed, viewed, copied or distributed:
This eBook is for the use of anyone anywhere in the United
States and most other parts of the world at no cost and with
almost no restrictions whatsoever. You may copy it, give it away
or re-use it under the terms of the Project Gutenberg License
included with this eBook or online at www.gutenberg.org. If you
are not located in the United States, you will have to check the
laws of the country where you are located before using this
eBook.

1.E.2. If an individual Project Gutenberg™ electronic work is derived


from texts not protected by U.S. copyright law (does not contain a
notice indicating that it is posted with permission of the copyright
holder), the work can be copied and distributed to anyone in the
United States without paying any fees or charges. If you are
redistributing or providing access to a work with the phrase “Project
Gutenberg” associated with or appearing on the work, you must
comply either with the requirements of paragraphs 1.E.1 through
1.E.7 or obtain permission for the use of the work and the Project
Gutenberg™ trademark as set forth in paragraphs 1.E.8 or 1.E.9.

1.E.3. If an individual Project Gutenberg™ electronic work is posted


with the permission of the copyright holder, your use and distribution
must comply with both paragraphs 1.E.1 through 1.E.7 and any
additional terms imposed by the copyright holder. Additional terms
will be linked to the Project Gutenberg™ License for all works posted
with the permission of the copyright holder found at the beginning of
this work.

1.E.4. Do not unlink or detach or remove the full Project


Gutenberg™ License terms from this work, or any files containing a
part of this work or any other work associated with Project
Gutenberg™.

1.E.5. Do not copy, display, perform, distribute or redistribute this


electronic work, or any part of this electronic work, without
prominently displaying the sentence set forth in paragraph 1.E.1 with
active links or immediate access to the full terms of the Project
Gutenberg™ License.
1.E.6. You may convert to and distribute this work in any binary,
compressed, marked up, nonproprietary or proprietary form,
including any word processing or hypertext form. However, if you
provide access to or distribute copies of a Project Gutenberg™ work
in a format other than “Plain Vanilla ASCII” or other format used in
the official version posted on the official Project Gutenberg™ website
(www.gutenberg.org), you must, at no additional cost, fee or expense
to the user, provide a copy, a means of exporting a copy, or a means
of obtaining a copy upon request, of the work in its original “Plain
Vanilla ASCII” or other form. Any alternate format must include the
full Project Gutenberg™ License as specified in paragraph 1.E.1.

1.E.7. Do not charge a fee for access to, viewing, displaying,


performing, copying or distributing any Project Gutenberg™ works
unless you comply with paragraph 1.E.8 or 1.E.9.

1.E.8. You may charge a reasonable fee for copies of or providing


access to or distributing Project Gutenberg™ electronic works
provided that:

• You pay a royalty fee of 20% of the gross profits you derive from
the use of Project Gutenberg™ works calculated using the
method you already use to calculate your applicable taxes. The
fee is owed to the owner of the Project Gutenberg™ trademark,
but he has agreed to donate royalties under this paragraph to
the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation. Royalty
payments must be paid within 60 days following each date on
which you prepare (or are legally required to prepare) your
periodic tax returns. Royalty payments should be clearly marked
as such and sent to the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive
Foundation at the address specified in Section 4, “Information
about donations to the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive
Foundation.”

• You provide a full refund of any money paid by a user who


notifies you in writing (or by e-mail) within 30 days of receipt that
s/he does not agree to the terms of the full Project Gutenberg™
License. You must require such a user to return or destroy all
copies of the works possessed in a physical medium and
discontinue all use of and all access to other copies of Project
Gutenberg™ works.

• You provide, in accordance with paragraph 1.F.3, a full refund of


any money paid for a work or a replacement copy, if a defect in
the electronic work is discovered and reported to you within 90
days of receipt of the work.

• You comply with all other terms of this agreement for free
distribution of Project Gutenberg™ works.

1.E.9. If you wish to charge a fee or distribute a Project Gutenberg™


electronic work or group of works on different terms than are set
forth in this agreement, you must obtain permission in writing from
the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation, the manager of
the Project Gutenberg™ trademark. Contact the Foundation as set
forth in Section 3 below.

1.F.

1.F.1. Project Gutenberg volunteers and employees expend


considerable effort to identify, do copyright research on, transcribe
and proofread works not protected by U.S. copyright law in creating
the Project Gutenberg™ collection. Despite these efforts, Project
Gutenberg™ electronic works, and the medium on which they may
be stored, may contain “Defects,” such as, but not limited to,
incomplete, inaccurate or corrupt data, transcription errors, a
copyright or other intellectual property infringement, a defective or
damaged disk or other medium, a computer virus, or computer
codes that damage or cannot be read by your equipment.

1.F.2. LIMITED WARRANTY, DISCLAIMER OF DAMAGES - Except


for the “Right of Replacement or Refund” described in paragraph
1.F.3, the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation, the owner
of the Project Gutenberg™ trademark, and any other party
distributing a Project Gutenberg™ electronic work under this
agreement, disclaim all liability to you for damages, costs and
expenses, including legal fees. YOU AGREE THAT YOU HAVE NO
REMEDIES FOR NEGLIGENCE, STRICT LIABILITY, BREACH OF
WARRANTY OR BREACH OF CONTRACT EXCEPT THOSE
PROVIDED IN PARAGRAPH 1.F.3. YOU AGREE THAT THE
FOUNDATION, THE TRADEMARK OWNER, AND ANY
DISTRIBUTOR UNDER THIS AGREEMENT WILL NOT BE LIABLE
TO YOU FOR ACTUAL, DIRECT, INDIRECT, CONSEQUENTIAL,
PUNITIVE OR INCIDENTAL DAMAGES EVEN IF YOU GIVE
NOTICE OF THE POSSIBILITY OF SUCH DAMAGE.

1.F.3. LIMITED RIGHT OF REPLACEMENT OR REFUND - If you


discover a defect in this electronic work within 90 days of receiving it,
you can receive a refund of the money (if any) you paid for it by
sending a written explanation to the person you received the work
from. If you received the work on a physical medium, you must
return the medium with your written explanation. The person or entity
that provided you with the defective work may elect to provide a
replacement copy in lieu of a refund. If you received the work
electronically, the person or entity providing it to you may choose to
give you a second opportunity to receive the work electronically in
lieu of a refund. If the second copy is also defective, you may
demand a refund in writing without further opportunities to fix the
problem.

1.F.4. Except for the limited right of replacement or refund set forth in
paragraph 1.F.3, this work is provided to you ‘AS-IS’, WITH NO
OTHER WARRANTIES OF ANY KIND, EXPRESS OR IMPLIED,
INCLUDING BUT NOT LIMITED TO WARRANTIES OF
MERCHANTABILITY OR FITNESS FOR ANY PURPOSE.

1.F.5. Some states do not allow disclaimers of certain implied


warranties or the exclusion or limitation of certain types of damages.
If any disclaimer or limitation set forth in this agreement violates the
law of the state applicable to this agreement, the agreement shall be
interpreted to make the maximum disclaimer or limitation permitted
by the applicable state law. The invalidity or unenforceability of any
provision of this agreement shall not void the remaining provisions.
1.F.6. INDEMNITY - You agree to indemnify and hold the
Foundation, the trademark owner, any agent or employee of the
Foundation, anyone providing copies of Project Gutenberg™
electronic works in accordance with this agreement, and any
volunteers associated with the production, promotion and distribution
of Project Gutenberg™ electronic works, harmless from all liability,
costs and expenses, including legal fees, that arise directly or
indirectly from any of the following which you do or cause to occur:
(a) distribution of this or any Project Gutenberg™ work, (b)
alteration, modification, or additions or deletions to any Project
Gutenberg™ work, and (c) any Defect you cause.

Section 2. Information about the Mission of


Project Gutenberg™
Project Gutenberg™ is synonymous with the free distribution of
electronic works in formats readable by the widest variety of
computers including obsolete, old, middle-aged and new computers.
It exists because of the efforts of hundreds of volunteers and
donations from people in all walks of life.

Volunteers and financial support to provide volunteers with the


assistance they need are critical to reaching Project Gutenberg™’s
goals and ensuring that the Project Gutenberg™ collection will
remain freely available for generations to come. In 2001, the Project
Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation was created to provide a
secure and permanent future for Project Gutenberg™ and future
generations. To learn more about the Project Gutenberg Literary
Archive Foundation and how your efforts and donations can help,
see Sections 3 and 4 and the Foundation information page at
www.gutenberg.org.

Section 3. Information about the Project


Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation
The Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation is a non-profit
501(c)(3) educational corporation organized under the laws of the
state of Mississippi and granted tax exempt status by the Internal
Revenue Service. The Foundation’s EIN or federal tax identification
number is 64-6221541. Contributions to the Project Gutenberg
Literary Archive Foundation are tax deductible to the full extent
permitted by U.S. federal laws and your state’s laws.

The Foundation’s business office is located at 809 North 1500 West,


Salt Lake City, UT 84116, (801) 596-1887. Email contact links and up
to date contact information can be found at the Foundation’s website
and official page at www.gutenberg.org/contact

Section 4. Information about Donations to


the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive
Foundation
Project Gutenberg™ depends upon and cannot survive without
widespread public support and donations to carry out its mission of
increasing the number of public domain and licensed works that can
be freely distributed in machine-readable form accessible by the
widest array of equipment including outdated equipment. Many small
donations ($1 to $5,000) are particularly important to maintaining tax
exempt status with the IRS.

The Foundation is committed to complying with the laws regulating


charities and charitable donations in all 50 states of the United
States. Compliance requirements are not uniform and it takes a
considerable effort, much paperwork and many fees to meet and
keep up with these requirements. We do not solicit donations in
locations where we have not received written confirmation of
compliance. To SEND DONATIONS or determine the status of
compliance for any particular state visit www.gutenberg.org/donate.

While we cannot and do not solicit contributions from states where


we have not met the solicitation requirements, we know of no
prohibition against accepting unsolicited donations from donors in
such states who approach us with offers to donate.

International donations are gratefully accepted, but we cannot make


any statements concerning tax treatment of donations received from
outside the United States. U.S. laws alone swamp our small staff.

Please check the Project Gutenberg web pages for current donation
methods and addresses. Donations are accepted in a number of
other ways including checks, online payments and credit card
donations. To donate, please visit: www.gutenberg.org/donate.

Section 5. General Information About Project


Gutenberg™ electronic works
Professor Michael S. Hart was the originator of the Project
Gutenberg™ concept of a library of electronic works that could be
freely shared with anyone. For forty years, he produced and
distributed Project Gutenberg™ eBooks with only a loose network of
volunteer support.

Project Gutenberg™ eBooks are often created from several printed


editions, all of which are confirmed as not protected by copyright in
the U.S. unless a copyright notice is included. Thus, we do not
necessarily keep eBooks in compliance with any particular paper
edition.

Most people start at our website which has the main PG search
facility: www.gutenberg.org.

This website includes information about Project Gutenberg™,


including how to make donations to the Project Gutenberg Literary
Archive Foundation, how to help produce our new eBooks, and how
to subscribe to our email newsletter to hear about new eBooks.

You might also like