Full download Today’s Moral Issues: Classic and Contemporary Perspectives, 7th edition 7th Edition, (Ebook PDF) file pdf all chapter on 2024

You might also like

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 44

Today’s Moral Issues: Classic and

Contemporary Perspectives, 7th edition


7th Edition, (Ebook PDF)
Visit to download the full and correct content document:
https://ebookmass.com/product/todays-moral-issues-classic-and-contemporary-persp
ectives-7th-edition-7th-edition-ebook-pdf/
More products digital (pdf, epub, mobi) instant
download maybe you interests ...

(eBook PDF) Gendered Voices, Feminist Visions: Classic


and Contemporary Readings 7th Edition

https://ebookmass.com/product/ebook-pdf-gendered-voices-feminist-
visions-classic-and-contemporary-readings-7th-edition/

School and Society: Historical and Contemporary


Perspectives 7th Edition, (Ebook PDF)

https://ebookmass.com/product/school-and-society-historical-and-
contemporary-perspectives-7th-edition-ebook-pdf/

Gendered Voices, Feminist Visions: Classic and


Contemporary Readings 7th Edition Susan M. Shaw

https://ebookmass.com/product/gendered-voices-feminist-visions-
classic-and-contemporary-readings-7th-edition-susan-m-shaw/

(eTextbook PDF) for Doing Ethics: Moral Reasoning,


Theory, and Contemporary Issues 5th Edition

https://ebookmass.com/product/etextbook-pdf-for-doing-ethics-
moral-reasoning-theory-and-contemporary-issues-5th-edition/
Doing Ethics: Moral Reasoning, Theory, and Contemporary
Issues (Fifth Edition)

https://ebookmass.com/product/doing-ethics-moral-reasoning-
theory-and-contemporary-issues-fifth-edition/

(eTextbook PDF) for Curriculum: Foundations,


Principles, and Issues 7th Edition

https://ebookmass.com/product/etextbook-pdf-for-curriculum-
foundations-principles-and-issues-7th-edition/

Contemporary World History 7th Edition William J.


Duiker

https://ebookmass.com/product/contemporary-world-history-7th-
edition-william-j-duiker/

Gender: Psychological Perspectives, Seventh Edition 7th


Edition, (Ebook PDF)

https://ebookmass.com/product/gender-psychological-perspectives-
seventh-edition-7th-edition-ebook-pdf/

Contemporary Oral and Maxillofacial Surgery 7th Edition

https://ebookmass.com/product/contemporary-oral-and-
maxillofacial-surgery-7th-edition/
Today’s Moral Issues, Seventh Edition, combines theoretical and practical Seventh Seventh Edition
readings on four general themes: first principles, liberty, rights and responsibilities, Edition
and justice and equality. The theoretical readings from classical philosophy, which
appear at the beginning of each of the four parts of the book, are closely related
to the contemporary readings that follow, which cover “hot button” issues of

Classic & Contemporary Perspectives


interest to today’s students.

TODAy’S
New in the Seventh Edition:
• A new section on gay marriage, one of the most contentious issues of
current politics, has been added.
• The Questions for Reflection that follow each reading have been expanded
and reworked.
• New selections are included from R. G. Frey, the World Commission on

Moral Issues
Environment and Development, Thomas Nagel, Francis Beckwith, Rosalind
Hursthouse, Stanley Kurtz, Andrew Koppelman, Maggie Gallagher, Toon
Quaghebeur, Bernadette Dierckx de Casterlé, Chris Gastmans, Carol Steiker,
Amartya Sen, Elizabeth Anderson, Robert Rector, Rachel Sheffield, and
Michael Huemer. T ODAy’S
What Instructors are Saying about Today’s Moral Issues:
“Overall, I think that the Bonevac text is an excellent choice for my course. . . .
Moral Issues

MD DALIM #1174741 12/17/11 CYAN MAG YELO BLK


The book strikes a good balance between the theory and the applied issues.”
—Tracie Mahaffey, Florida State University

“ I would say that you really can’t go wrong with this text. It’s an extremely
Classic & Contemporary Perspectives
versatile text for a wide range of ethics-oriented courses.”
—Stephen Carey, Virginia Commonwealth University

“The topics are framed by ‘first principles’ sections, which introduce students
to classical sources in the field. These, together with the broad range of topics
covered, make it the best on the market.”

Bonevac
—Nicholas Power, University of West Florida

Daniel Bonevac
g
PREFACE

This book is a text for courses on contemporary strikes students as dry and irrelevant, while the prac-
moral issues. Such courses assume that philosophy tical part remains confusing or, at best, an exercise in
has something important to contribute to contempo- applying theory.
rary moral problems. They try to bring philosophi- This book tries to resolve the dilemma by tying
cal theories to bear on practical questions. From one theoretical and practical considerations together.
point of view, this seems difficult. Philosophy is in Today’s Moral Issues combines theoretical and practi-
many ways the most abstract of all disciplines. The cal readings on four general themes: first principles,
questions it addresses are very general: What is real? liberty, rights and responsibilities, and justice and
How do we know? What should we do? But philoso- equality. The theoretical readings are closely related
phy is also the most practical of all disciplines. It aims to the contemporary readings that follow. I have
at wisdom. Living wisely, displaying good judgment, found that using philosophical texts helps students
understanding yourself and your surroundings— connect theory and practice, for writers such as
these offer immense benefits to all, no matter who Locke and Mill tend to be more concrete and practi-
they are, how they earn a living, or what kind of cal in outlook than most secondary discussions of
society they inhabit. Living wisely is a key to living their thought. Their motivations are not difficult for
well. For just that reason, Aristotle thought that phi- most students to understand. And I have edited the
losophy was the highest human activity and that the theoretical texts closely to bring students into direct
contemplative life was the highest and happiest form contact with their chief motivations and arguments.
of life possible for a human being. The classic and contemporary theoretical
Nevertheless, it is not always easy to bring theory approaches constitute a foundation for thinking
and practice together in the classroom. Philosophical about contemporary issues. Combining these texts
texts can be hard to read. Philosophers often write with discussions of contemporary problems lets stu-
primarily for each other. And arguments about con- dents see the dialectic between theory and practice
temporary issues are rarely reflective; the underlying in ethics. Faced with practical dilemmas and dis-
principles can be hard to discern. agreements, it is easy to see why ethical thinkers
Contemporary moral problems textbooks often have sought to construct theories. And contempo-
amplify these difficulties. They contain mostly papers rary issues provide opportunities not only to apply
by professional philosophers written for a profes- theories but also to test and evaluate them. Good
sional audience. They tend to omit underlying theo- students, I have found, attain not only a rich under-
retical approaches altogether or segregate them in a standing of the theories, the issues, and how they are
separate section of the book. The first strategy leaves related, but also a real sense of what ethical thinking
students with no moral compass. Students have trou- is all about.
ble abstracting ethical principles and methods from Today’s Moral Issues is unique in treating contem-
treatments of particular issues; even the best students porary moral issues in the context of both politi-
flounder when faced with issues that have not been cal philosophy and ethics. Issues such as abortion,
treated explicitly in class. The result is that students euthanasia, and the environment have political as
emerge with only the vaguest idea of what ethical well as personal dimensions. Others, such as free-
thinking is. The second strategy divides courses into dom of speech, capital punishment, and economic,
two parts that are hard to unify. The theory usually racial, sexual, and global equality, are almost entirely
vii

bon38219_fm_i-xvi.indd vii 12/28/11 4:28 PM


viii Preface

political. To treat them adequately, one must consider f. suggested readings


the proper ends of government and the bounds of g. relevant court cases
state action.
h. Web links to other sources of information on
contemporary issues
New Features i. a guide to writing philosophical essays
This edition retains the virtues of earlier editions. j. tips on multimedia presentations
It combines theoretical and practical treatments of k. PowerPoint slides for each section of the text
ethical and political issues from a wide variety of per-
spectives and sources, including court cases, journal-
ists, public figures, public policy researchers, and Acknowledgments
scientists as well as philosophers.
This edition also has some new virtues. It differs This book and the ideas behind it have evolved con-
from earlier editions in some important ways: siderably during the thirty years I have been teaching
contemporary moral issues courses at the University
1. Among the most contentious issues of current of Pittsburgh and the University of Texas at Austin.
politics is gay marriage. I have expanded the book I am grateful to the many instructors, teaching assis-
to include it. tants, and students who have used earlier versions
2. More than 20 percent of the readings are new to and helped me refine them. I am particularly grateful
this edition. to the more than 10,000 students who have taken
3. In the Theoretical Approaches sections, I have my contemporary moral problems course at the Uni-
added readings from Confucius. In the sec- versity of Texas at Austin. They have taught me much
tions dealing with issues, I have added pieces about what a course on moral issues ought to be.
by R. G. Frey, the World Commission on Envi- I especially want to thank Nicholas Asher and
ronment and Development, Thomas Nagel, Stephen Phillips, who have team-taught courses
Francis Beckwith, Rosalind Hursthouse, Stan- on contemporary moral problems with me. Their
ley Kurtz, Andrew Koppelman, Maggie Galla- ideas have found expression here in more ways than
gher, Toon Quaghebeur, Bernadete Dierckx de I can distinguish. I am also grateful for the helpful
Casterlé, and Chris Gastmans, Carol Steiker, criticism and advice I have received throughout the
Amartya Sen, Elizabeth Anderson, Robert Rec- years from Randy Mayes, California State University,
tor and Rachel Sheffield, and Michael Huemer. Sacramento; Bill Myers, Birmingham Southern
College; David Bradshaw, University of Kentucky;
4. I have reworked and greatly expanded the Ques-
and Jonathan Davis, University of Texas at Austin.
tions for Reflection, especially in the theoretical
I would like to thank the reviewers whose com-
sections.
ments have helped me clarify my own thinking and
5. The Web page (http://bonevac.info/tmi) that accom- decide what issues and readings to include: for the
panies the book has been expanded. It includes first edition, L. E. Andrade, Illinois State Univer-
many features to help both students and instruc- sity; Linda Bomstad, California State University,
tors, including Sacramento; Karen Hanson, Indiana University; and
a. sample course syllabi Anita Silvers, San Francisco State University; for
b. extensive class notes for all sections of the book, the second edition, Stephanie Beardman, Rutgers
with links to relevant parts of philosophical University; Ray Cebik, University of Tennessee,
texts (where they are public domain and avail- Knoxville; Deirdre Golash, American University;
able online) Patrick Lee, Franciscan University of Steubenville;
Aaron Meskin, Rutgers University; Sharon Sytsma,
c. a study guide summarizing key points
Northern Illinois University; and Nathan Tierney,
d. a comprehensive glossary of terms California Lutheran University; for the third edition,
e. practice exams Naomi Azck, University of Albany, State University

bon38219_fm_i-xvi.indd viii 12/28/11 4:28 PM


Preface ix

of New York; Stephen Carey, Virginia Common- • Nicholas Power, University of West Florida
wealth University; Scott Lehman, University of • Stephen Carey, Virginia Commonwealth University
Connecticut; A. P. Roark, University of Washington;
• Tracie Mahaffey, Florida State University
and Stewart Shapiro, Ohio State University at New-
ark; for the fourth edition, Abrol O. Fairweather, • John Messerly, Shoreline Community College
CSU, Hayward; A. R. Molina, University of Miami; • Sean Stidd, Wayne State University
Barbara Montero, NYU; Lawrence Pasternack, • Corine Sutherland, Golden West College
Oklahoma State University; Janice Staab, Southern
• Dan Lioy, Marylhurst University
Illinois University; Lawrence Stark, State University
of New York at Albany; for the fifth edition, Jean I am grateful to all of those at McGraw-Hill who
Axelrod Cahan, University of Nebraska, Lincoln; have supported this book and worked to present my
Barbara Lowe, St. John Fisher College; Joseph Pap- ideas. I want especially to thank my editors. Jim Bull
pin III, University of South Carolina; and Wendy A. was vital to the first two editions, and Ken King sim-
Ritch, Raritan Valley Community College; for the ilarly vital to the next two. I am also deeply grateful
sixth edition, Hannah Phelps, Pacific Lutheran Uni- to Jessica Cannavo, sponsoring editor; develop-
versity; Diane Bowser, The Art Institute of Pittsburg; ment editor, Craig Leonard; marketing coordinator:
Lawrence Stratton, Villanova University; Jack Bayne, Angela R. FitzPatrick; copyeditor, Kay Mikel; project
University of Massachusetts, Boston; Robert Pielke, manager, Melissa M. Leick; design coordinator,
El Camino College; and Peter Marton, Salem State Margarite Reynolds; and Louis Swaim, Buyer, for
College; and, for the seventh edition, their support throughout my work on this project.

bon38219_fm_i-xvi.indd ix 12/28/11 4:28 PM


bon38219_fm_i-xvi.indd x 12/28/11 4:28 PM
g
CONTENTS

Preface vii

INTRODUCTION MORAL ARGUMENTS 1

Arguments 1
Making Moral Arguments 2
Exceptions to Moral Principles 4

PART I FIRST PRINCIPLES 7

THEORETICAL APPROACHES 13
Confucius, from The Analects 13
Aristotle, from Nicomachean Ethics 17
St. Thomas Aquinas, from Summa Theologica 23
David Hume, from A Treatise of Human Nature 27
Immanuel Kant, from Fundamental Principles of the Metaphysics of
Morals 31
Jeremy Bentham, from An Introduction to the Principles of Morals and
Legislation 43
John Stuart Mill, from Utilitarianism 50
Nel Noddings, from Caring: A Feminine Approach to Ethics and Moral
Education 55

S E X U A L B E H AV I O R 6 0
Bertrand Russell, Our Sexual Ethics 61
Thomas A. Mappes, Sexual Morality and the
Concept of Using Another Person 66
Roger Scruton, from Sexual Desire 73

xi

bon38219_fm_i-xvi.indd xi 12/28/11 4:28 PM


xii Contents

S E X U A L O R I E N T AT I O N A N D G AY M A R R I A G E 7 7
Justice Byron White, Majority Opinion in Bowers v. Hardwick 79
Justice Anthony Kennedy, Majority Opinion in Lawrence et al.
v. Texas 82
Massachusetts Chief Justice Margaret H. Marshall
and Justice Robert J. Cordy, Majority and Dissenting Opinions in
Goodridge v. Department of Public Health 87
Stanley Kurtz, The Libertarian Question 102
Andrew Koppelman, from The Decline and Fall of the Case against
Same-Sex Marriage 106
Maggie Gallagher, from (How) Will Gay
Marriage Weaken Marriage as a Social Institution:
A Reply to Andrew Koppelman 112

ANIMALS 119
International League of the Rights of Animals, Universal Declaration
of the Rights of Animals 121
Peter Singer, from Animal Liberation 123
Tom Regan, The Case for Animal Rights 130
R. G. Frey, Moral Community and Animal Research in Medicine 134

THE ENVIRONMENT 143


Garrett Hardin, from The Tragedy of the Commons 146
World Commission on Environment and Development, from Our
Common Future: Report of the World Commission on Environment and
Development 149
Daniel Bonevac, Is Sustainability Sustainable? 154

PART II LIBERT Y 163

THEORETICAL APPROACHES 165


Aristotle, from Nicomachean Ethics 165
John Stuart Mill, from On Liberty 168

D R U G L E G A L I Z AT I O N 1 7 7
Milton Friedman, An Open Letter to Bill Bennett 178

bon38219_fm_i-xvi.indd xii 12/28/11 4:28 PM


Contents xiii

William J. Bennett, A Response to Milton Friedman 181


Ethan A. Nadelmann, The Case for Legalization 184
James Q. Wilson, Against the Legalization of Drugs 190

PORNOGRAPHY 197
Chief Justice Warren Burger and Justice William O. Douglas,
Majority and Dissenting Opinions in Miller v. California 199
Catharine MacKinnon, Pornography, Civil Rights, and Speech 205
The Attorney General’s Commission on Pornography, The Question
of Harm 209
Wendy MCElroy, from Sexual Correctness 216

O F F E N S I V E S P E E C H A N D B E H AV I O R 2 2 3
Plato, from The Republic 226
John Stuart Mill, from On Liberty 232
Stanley Fish, from There’s No Such Thing as Free Speech, and It’s a Good
Thing, Too 237
Thomas Nagel, Personal Rights and Public Space 243
Chief Justice John Roberts and Justice Paul Stevens, Majority and
Dissenting Opinions in Morse v. Frederick 248

PART III RIGHTS AND RESPONSIBILITIES 259

THEORETICAL APPROACHES 261


Thomas Hobbes, from Leviathan 261
John Locke, from Second Treatise of Government 266
Edmund Burke, from Reflections on the Revolution in
France 273
John Stuart Mill, from Utilitarianism 282
United Nations, Universal Declaration of Human Rights 286

A B O RT I O N 2 9 0
Justice Harry Blackmun, Majority Opinion in Roe v. Wade 292
Judith Jarvis Thomson, A Defense of Abortion 297
Mary Anne Warren, On the Moral and Legal Status of Abortion 307

bon38219_fm_i-xvi.indd xiii 12/28/11 4:28 PM


xiv Contents

Don Marquis, Why Abortion Is Immoral 318


Rosalind Hursthouse, Virtue Theory and Abortion 327
Francis J. Beckwith, Personal Bodily Rights, Abortion,
and Unplugging the Violinist 333
Alexander R. Pruss, I Was Once a Fetus: That Is Why Abortion Is
Wrong 342

EUTHANASIA AND PHYSICIAN-ASSISTED


SUICIDE 350
Supreme Court of New Jersey, Matter of Quinlan 352
J. Gay-Williams, The Wrongfulness of Euthanasia 357
Ronald Dworkin, Thomas Nagel, Robert Nozick, John Rawls,
Thomas Scanlon, and Judith Jarvis Thomson, The Brief of the
Amici Curiae 360
Chief Justice William Rehnquist, Majority Opinion in Washington
et al. v. Glucksberg et al. 366
Toon Quaghebeur, Bernadette Dierckx de Casterlé,
and Chris Gastmans, Nursing and Euthanasia: A Review of Argument-
Based Ethics Literature 372

C A P I TA L P U N I S H M E N T 3 7 9
Cesare Beccaria, from On Crimes and Punishments 381
Justice William Brennan, Concurring Opinion in Furman v.
Georgia 386
Justices Stewart, Powell, and Stevens, Majority Opinion in Gregg v.
Georgia 388
Ernest van den Haag, from The Death Penalty: A Debate 392
Hugo Adam Bedau, The Case against the Death Penalty 396
Cass R. Sunstein and Adrian Vermeule, Is Capital Punishment Morally
Required? The Relevance of Life-Life Tradeoffs 403
Carol S. Steiker, No, Capital Punishment Is Not Morally Required:
Deterrence, Deontology, and the Death Penalty 415

WA R 4 2 5
St. Thomas Aquinas, Whether It Is Always Sinful to Wage War? 427
Francisco de Vitoria, from The Law of War on Indians 429
Hugo Grotius, from On the Law of War and Peace 432

bon38219_fm_i-xvi.indd xiv 12/28/11 4:28 PM


Contents xv

Carl von Clausewitz, On the Nature of War 438


Mahatma Gandhi, Non-Violence in Various Aspects 442
Richard A. Posner and Gary S. Becker, Preventive War 446

PART IV JUSTICE AND EQUALITY 449

THEORETICAL APPROACHES 451


Aristotle, from Nicomachean Ethics 451
Aristotle, from Politics 453
John Locke, from Second Treatise of Government 455
Jean-Jacques Rousseau, from Discourse on the Origin of Inequality 466
Jean-Jacques Rousseau, from On the Social Contract 474
Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels, from Manifesto of the Communist
Party 478
Karl Marx, from Estranged Labour, Economic and Philosophical
Manuscripts of 1844 484
Karl Marx, from Critique of the Gotha Program 489
John Rawls, Justice as Fairness 492
Robert Nozick, from Anarchy, State, and Utopia 497

ECONOMIC EQUALITY 505


John Stuart Mill, from Principles of Political Economy 507
John Hospers, What Libertarianism Is 510
Amartya Sen, Equality of What? 516
Charles Murray, from Losing Ground: American Social Policy,
1950–1980 520
Elizabeth S. Anderson, What Is the Point of Equality? 529
Robert Rector and Rachel Sheffield, Air Conditioning, Cable TV, and an
Xbox: What Is Poverty in the United States Today? 540

A F F I R M AT I V E A C T I O N 5 5 4
Chief Justice Earl Warren, Majority Opinion in Brown v. Board of
Education 556
Justice Lewis Powell, Majority Opinion in Regents of the University of
California v. Bakke 559

bon38219_fm_i-xvi.indd xv 12/28/11 4:28 PM


xvi Contents

Antonin Scalia, The Disease as a Cure 567


Bernard R. Boxill, from Blacks and Social Justice 573
Thomas Sowell, “Affirmative Action”: A Worldwide Disaster 579
Chief Justice William Rehnquist, Majority Opinion in Gratz et al. v.
Bollinger et al. 595
Justice Sandra Day O’Connor, Majority Opinion in Grutter v. Bollinger
et al. 600

I M M I G R AT I O N 6 0 9
Immanuel Kant, from Perpetual Peace 611
Garrett Hardin, Living on a Lifeboat 616
Robert D. Putnam, E Pluribus Unum: Diversity and Community in the
Twenty-First Century The 2006 Johan Skytte Prize Lecture 621
Michael Huemer, Is There a Right to Immigrate? 631

bon38219_fm_i-xvi.indd xvi 12/28/11 4:28 PM


INTRODUCTION
g
MORAL ARGUMENTS

This is a book about moral issues. What are moral Components of Arguments
issues? To answer this question, we need to consider
The initial assertions of an argument are its premises;
the definition of philosophy. If the word itself is any
the thesis that the argument tries to justify is its con-
guide, philosophy is the love of wisdom. A simple
clusion. Arguments consist of statements, sentences
definition of wisdom, in turn, is good judgment. Phi-
that can be true or false. Almost every sentence in this
losophy, then, is the love or pursuit of good judg-
book falls into this category. Statements are declara-
ment. Moral philosophy, or ethics, is the pursuit of
tive, in the indicative mood; they say something about
good judgment about character and action—about
the way the world is, correctly or incorrectly.
what kind of person to be and about what to do. Eth-
Here, for example, is a simple argument:
ics addresses questions about virtue and vice, good
and bad, right and wrong. (1) Stealing is wrong.
Such questions, clearly, have varied answers; they ∴ Stealing this book is wrong.
are often the subject of controversy and debate. The
(This format lists the premises in the order in which
moral issues considered in this book—abortion,
they are given and then gives the conclusion. The
euthanasia, pornography, capital punishment, affir-
symbol ∴ means “therefore.”)
mative action, and many others—are among the
How can we recognize arguments? The premises
most controversial our society faces. Most of this
of an argument are meant to support the conclusion.
book consists of moral arguments, in which a moral
We can recognize arguments, then, by recognizing
issue is considered and a particular position is sup-
when some statements are offered in support of oth-
ported or a particular conclusion is reached through
ers. We can do this most easily, in turn, if we can dis-
reasoning.
tinguish premises from conclusions. But how can we
How can we think through moral issues carefully
pick out the conclusion of an argument? In English,
and systematically? How do we develop arguments
various words and phrases can signal the premises or
for ethical conclusions? These are questions that I
the conclusion of an argument.
attempt to answer in this introduction.
• Conclusion Indicators: therefore, thus, hence,
consequently, it follows that, in conclusion, as a
Arguments result, then, must, accordingly, this implies that,
this entails that, we may infer that
Arguments are bits of reasoning in language. Fre-
• Premise Indicators: because, as, for, since, given
quently, we think of arguments as conflicts. In that
that, for the reason that
sense, this book presents a series of arguments about
issues such as abortion, euthanasia, and affirmative Beware: These words and phrases have other uses as
action. But philosophers and logicians primarily use well.
“argument” in the sense that one argues for a conclu- Extended or complex arguments contain other argu-
sion. An argument starts with some assertions and ments. Simple arguments do not. Because extended
tries to justify a thesis. arguments are good only if the simple arguments

bon38219_intro_01-06.indd 1 12/22/11 11:04 AM


2 Introduction

within them are good, it is best to break extended A sound argument is a valid argument with true
arguments down into their simple components and premises. In any valid argument, the truth of the
analyze them separately. premises guarantees the truth of the conclusion, so a
sound argument also has a true conclusion. A cogent
argument is an inductively strong argument with
Validity and Soundness
true premises. In a cogent argument, the truth of the
To evaluate arguments, we need to ask, What dis- conclusion is likely but not guaranteed.
tinguishes good from bad arguments? What makes a Logic develops precise ways of determining
good argument good? whether arguments are valid (although the most
A good argument links its premises to its conclusion powerful ways of evaluating arguments are intui-
in the right way. In a (deductively) valid argument, the tive). An argument is valid if the truth of the prem-
truth of the premises guarantees the truth of the con- ises guarantees the truth of the conclusion. To show
clusion. If the premises are all true, then the conclusion that an argument is invalid, therefore, one needs to
has to be true. Or, equivalently, if the conclusion of a show that the premises could all be true while the
valid argument is false, at least one premise must also conclusion is false.
be false. Consider, for example, the argument There are two ways of showing that an argument
is invalid. The first, the direct method, is simply to
(2) All promises ought to be kept.
describe such a situation; that is, we can show an
Your promise to Joe is a promise.
argument to be invalid by depicting a possible cir-
∴ You ought to keep your promise to Joe.
cumstance in which the premises were all true but
In any circumstance in which the premises of this the conclusion was false.
argument are true, the conclusion must be true as The second way to show that an argument is
well. It is impossible to conceive of a state of affairs in invalid, devised by Aristotle, is based on the idea of
which, while all promises ought to be kept, and your form and is known as the method of counterexam-
promise to Joe is a promise, you nevertheless should ples. To show that an argument is invalid using this
not keep your promise to Joe. If it is false that you method, we must produce another argument of the
should keep your promise to Joe, then either there same form with true premises and a false conclusion.
are promises that shouldn’t be kept, or your “prom- This introduction is too short to present a detailed
ise” wasn’t a real promise. discussion of form. But Aristotle’s insight was that
Valid arguments are only one species of good validity is formal in the sense that arguments can be
argument. Others are inductively strong (or reliable). classified into certain general patterns, or forms, of
The truth of the premises of such an argument does which individual arguments are instances. An argu-
not guarantee the truth of its conclusion, but it does ment form is valid if and only if every instance of
make the truth of the conclusion probable. Consider, it is valid. More to the point, an argument form is
for example, this argument: invalid if and only if some instance of it is invalid.
To show that an argument form is invalid, then, find
(3) Every generous person I’ve ever known has also
an instance with true premises and a false conclu-
been kind.
sion. To show that an individual argument is invalid,
∴ All generous people are kind.
find an argument with true premises and a false con-
It is possible for the premise to be true while the clusion that shares the specific form of the original
conclusion is false. There may be generous but nasty argument: the most explicit form we can devise, dis-
people I’ve never met. So the argument is invalid. playing the most structure.
Nevertheless, the premise lends some support to the
conclusion. The argument is inductively strong; how
strong depends on how many generous people I’ve
known, among other things.
Making Moral Arguments
In general, good arguments not only are valid As we have seen, it is possible to attack an argument
or inductively strong but also have true premises. by showing that one of its premises is false. Even

bon38219_intro_01-06.indd 2 12/22/11 11:04 AM


Introduction 3

if the argument is valid or strong, such an attack take vacation whenever it won’t cause your cowork-
shows that it is not sound or cogent and undercuts ers any inconvenience (moral premise).
its conclusion.
Moral arguments typically have both moral and
factual premises. Some statements are factual or Arguing for a Moral Principle
descriptive. They say how the world is. Other state- (5) is a pattern for arguing to a particular moral con-
ments are evaluative, prescriptive, or normative. They clusion. But how can one argue for general moral
say how the world ought to be; more generally, they conclusions, such as the moral principles on which
evaluate how the world is, characterizing it as right such arguments rely? How, in other words, does one
or wrong, acceptable or unacceptable, delightful or support moral premises such as You ought to keep
dismal. They include specifically evaluative terms. your promises, You ought to return what you borrow
A moral argument is an argument with an evaluative when it’s due, or You may take vacation whenever it
conclusion. People who reach opposite conclusions won’t cause your coworkers any inconvenience?
may differ in moral principles, but they may also dif- In essence, there are two ways to argue for a moral
fer in factual assumptions. One of the chief purposes generalization: from above and from below. To argue
of a contemporary moral problems course is to teach from above, appeal to a more general moral prin-
people how to disentangle moral from factual issues. ciple. John Stuart Mill, for example, would argue
The distinction matters, because factual and moral as follows for the generalization, You ought to keep
conclusions require different kinds of support. your promises:
Consider a simple example:
(6) You ought to follow the rules that will maximize
(4) You promised to sublet the apartment. human happiness.
You should keep your promises.
Following the rule You ought to keep your
∴ You should sublet the apartment.
promises will maximize human happiness.
The first premise is factual. Whether you promised ∴ You ought to keep your promises.
to sublet the apartment is a matter of fact. If it is
Immanuel Kant would justify it differently:
disputed, we may ask about the facts: What exactly
did you say? Is there any agreement in writing? Did (7) You ought to treat others as ends, not merely as
you sign anything? Was it really this apartment? means.
The second premise, in contrast, is evaluative. It
Keeping a promise to someone treats that per-
speaks of how things ought to be, not how they
son as an end, but breaking one treats him or
are. Consequently, no amount of inquiry into the
her as a means to your ends.
facts can help us determine its truth or falsehood.
∴ You ought to keep your promises.
To justify it, we must appeal to more general moral
principles. Philosophers who prefer justifications from above
The general pattern of moral arguments for par- tend, like Mill and Kant, to search for a single, very
ticular conclusions is thus: general moral principle that can justify other prin-
ciples.
(5) Factual premise(s)
Moral principles may also be justified from
Moral premise(s)
below, by appeal to their instances. One could
∴ Moral conclusion
try to argue that it is wrong to break promises,
This is utterly familiar. You ought to return those for example, by generalizing from examples of
books to the library. Why? You borrowed them (fac- particular situations:
tual premise), they are due (factual premise), and (8) Say someone promises to marry you but
you ought to return what you borrow when it is due doesn’t show up at the altar; that would be wrong.
(moral premise). Or, you may take vacation the last Say Frank borrows money from you, promis-
week of April. Why? It won’t cause your coworkers ing insincerely to repay it, and then absconds; that
any inconvenience (factual premise), and you may would be wrong.

bon38219_intro_01-06.indd 3 12/22/11 11:04 AM


4 Introduction

Say the doctor makes an appointment to see you and (10) One should always keep one’s promises.
then goes to play golf instead; that would be wrong. ∴ If Herman promised to murder the entire
Say Joan agrees to pay you $1,000 for landscaping city council, he should do it.
her yard, you do the work, and she refuses to pay;
The absurdity of the conclusion shows that there is
that would be wrong.
something wrong with the premise.
∴ Breaking promises is wrong.
Many philosophers have objected to Kant’s opin-
or more specific kinds of situations: ion that lying is always wrong by constructing a simi-
(9) Someone who agrees to marry someone on a par- lar argument. Suppose that a distraught child runs to
ticular day should show up for the wedding. you begging for help. A homicidal maniac is chasing
her. You hide her in a closet. The maniac bangs on
Someone who borrows money ought to repay it.
your door and asks whether you know where she is.
Someone who makes an appointment ought to
Surely you should not tell the truth.
keep it.
Someone who signs a contract ought to fulfill it.
∴ Breaking promises is wrong.
Exceptions to Moral Principles
These arguments are not valid, but they are induc-
This example illustrates that most moral principles
tively strong if the examples are numerous and
have exceptions. Most moral principles are true other
diverse enough.
things being equal (in Latin, ceteris paribus), but not
The readings in this book contain many arguments
universally. Plato recognized this about promise
for moral principles, some from above, some from
keeping and telling the truth:
below. Arguments from above are important, for they
say something about why the moral principle holds. . . . are we to say that justice or right is simply to speak
Kant’s argument for promise keeping, for example, not the truth and to pay back any debt one may have con-
only concludes that promises should be kept but also tracted? Or are these same actions sometimes right
indicates that they should be kept because breaking and sometimes wrong? I mean this sort of thing, for
them treats others as means to your own ends. Mill’s example: everyone would surely agree that if a friend
argument, similarly, indicates that promise keeping is has deposited weapons with you when he was sane,
obligatory because it maximizes human happiness. and he asks for them when he is out of his mind, you
Arguments from below are also important, for they should not return them. The man who returns them
link principles to particular cases about which we is not doing right, nor is one who is willing to tell the
have strong moral intuitions. The more abstract and whole truth to a man in such a state. (Republic, 331c)*
general a moral principle is, the fewer intuitions we
Although Keep your promises and Tell the truth are
have about whether it is correct. Moral theories there-
good moral rules in general, they can be overridden
fore rely on both kinds of arguments.
or defeated by other moral considerations. For that
reason, they are called defeasible. Normally, you
Arguing against a Moral Principle
ought to keep your promises. Normally, you ought
How does one argue against a moral principle? One to tell the truth. But sometimes there are good rea-
tries to find a counterexample: an instance in which sons to break a promise or to lie, and then you have
the principle seems to give the wrong result. Is it a moral conflict.
always right to keep promises, for instance? One Philosophers often analyze such situations of moral
can try to find examples of promises that should not conflict in terms of prima facie duties. W. D. Ross
be kept. Recall that, in a valid argument, the truth defined “prima facie duty” as a “characteristic (quite
of the premises guarantees the truth of the conclu- distinct from that of being a duty proper) which an
sion, or, equivalently, the falsehood of the conclusion
guarantees the falsehood of at least one premise. One
can construct a valid argument from the principle to *Plato,The Republic, translated by Paul Shorey (Cambridge, Mass.:
a false conclusion: Loeb Classical Library, 1930).

bon38219_intro_01-06.indd 4 12/22/11 11:04 AM


Introduction 5

act has, in virtue of being of a certain kind (e.g., the You have an actual obligation not to return the
keeping of a promise), of being an act which would weapons.
be a duty proper if it were not at the same time of You cannot be obliged, actually, all things con-
another kind which is morally significant.”* A prima sidered, both to return the weapons and not
facie obligation, that is, holds under normal circum- to return them.
stances; it holds all other things being equal, becom- Because conditional prima facie obligations can
ing actual—an obligation all things considered, or, conflict, this pair of statements is consistent:
in Ross’s terms, “a duty proper”—unless some other
(12) You have a prima facie obligation to return the
moral consideration intervenes.
weapons.
Prima facie obligations offer a way to explain the
You have a prima facie obligation not to return
force of rules while allowing for exceptions. The idea,
the weapons.
in essence, is that a prima facie rule applies unless
some other rule conflicts with it. John Stuart Mill’s In general, you have a prima facie obligation to
secondary principles are paradigms of prima facie do something whenever the circumstances trigger a
principles: They dictate obligations unless they come defeasible moral rule. In Plato’s case, there are defea-
into conflict. In that case, Mill stipulates, the prin- sible rules that you ought to keep your promises and
ciple of utility, the sole rule in his system that has an that you ought to prevent harm. Your promise gives
absolute rather than prima facie character, resolves rise to the prima facie obligation to return the weap-
the conflict. This indicates a key difference between ons; your friend’s madness gives rise to the prima
actual and prima facie obligation: Prima facie obliga- facie obligation not to return them.
tions can conflict, whereas actual obligations cannot. Moral conflicts such as those Plato describes have
If a homicidal maniac asks whether you know where spurred philosophers to devise moral theories to
an innocent child is hiding, there is a moral conflict: help us compare different kinds of moral consider-
You have a prima facie obligation to tell the truth and ations and resolve conflicts generated by them.
another to tell a lie. Only one can be actual—what Seeing that moral considerations can come into
you ought actually to do in that situation, all things conflict helps to dissolve some of the motivation for
considered. Saving a life is more important than relativism. In morality, it is often true that one per-
never telling a lie, so your obligation to lie is actual, son or culture sees things one way and another sees
overriding your obligation to tell the truth. them quite differently. But even within the view of a
Let’s revisit Plato’s puzzle about returning weapons single person and culture, there are many different
to a friend who is out of his mind. Because uncondi- perspectives, which it is the task of morality to relate,
tional statements of actual obligation cannot conflict, evaluate, and, in particular situations, reconcile. Rea-
this pair is inconsistent: sonable people can differ on how to reconcile them.
That is what makes a book like this both possible
(11) You have an actual obligation to return the
and important.
weapons.

*W.D. Ross, The Right and the Good (Oxford: Oxford University
Press, 1930), 19.

bon38219_intro_01-06.indd 5 12/22/11 11:04 AM


bon38219_intro_01-06.indd 6 12/22/11 11:04 AM
PART I
g
FIRST PRINCIPLES

Most of our moral judgments concern particular things. The distinction between these kinds of assertions
We judge certain actions and certain people good or matters, for we resolve disagreements about them in
bad. There are many gradations: Acts or people may very different ways. Suppose, for example, that you
be heroic, splendid, admirable, acceptable, indifferent, challenge my first premise. You deny, in other words,
unsatisfactory, despicable, or horrible, to mention just that Jennifer committed a murder. We might resolve
a few moral adjectives. There are also many dimen- our disagreement by clarifying our use of words and
sions of moral consideration: Acts or people may be investigating the facts. If I defend my premise with
honest, kind, loyal, trustworthy, noble, brave, gener- further premises:
ous, self-controlled, gentle, friendly, witty, pleasant,
4. Murder is killing a human being with malice
helpful, effective, efficient, or considerate, to mention
aforethought.
just a few positive attributes. Usually, we apply these
to particular actions or to particular people. 5. Jennifer killed Michael.
When people disagree about a moral judgment, 6. Michael was human.
they try to justify their views. They do this by con- 7. Jennifer intended to do Michael harm.
structing an argument that appeals to moral prin-
ciples. Suppose, for example, that Jennifer killed you might challenge my definition of murder (4) or
Michael by breaking a baseball bat over his head. my description of the facts (5, 6, and 7). We might
And say that you and I disagree about the morality of proceed to investigate whether Jennifer was really the
the act. I think it was wrong; you think it was justifi- killer and Michael really the victim; whether Jennifer
able. I might try to justify my judgment by construct- intended to harm Michael or killed him accidentally;
ing a simple argument: whether Michael was human or a robot; and whether
my definition of murder is correct. All these issues
1. Jennifer’s killing Michael was murder. (Fact) concern definitions or matters of fact.
2. Murder is always wrong. (Moral principle) If you challenge my second premise, however,
3. Therefore, Jennifer’s killing Michael was wrong. investigating matters of fact cannot resolve our dis-
(Moral conclusion) agreement. We differ not on how the world is but
on how it ought to be. And, as David Hume stresses,
An argument for a particular moral conclusion gen- there is no way to derive ought from is; no amount
erally contains both factual and moral premises, just of factual information can determine how the world
as this one does. The first premise is factual; it pur- ought to be. To justify my premise, I must appeal
ports to describe the way the world is. The second to some broader moral principle—and ultimately,
premise, in contrast, is moral. It does not describe many philosophers have thought, to a first, most
the world as it is but evaluates a general category fundamental moral principle from which all others
of action. Assertions like the first premise are often follow. The thinkers of the Enlightenment, espe-
called factual or descriptive. Those like the second cially, saw that if we could establish and agree upon
premise or the conclusion are often called evaluative, a first principle of morality, all our disagreements
prescriptive, or normative. would concern definitions and matters of fact and

bon38219_pt1_007-162.indd 7 12/28/11 8:14 PM


8 First Principles

thus would be resolvable by investigation. Morality appeal to an instrumental good, the questioner can
would lend itself to scientific inquiry as much as ask in turn why you want it.
anything else. Aristotle contends that people desire only one
The search for a first principle of morality has thing for its own sake and never for the sake of some-
other sources. One stems from the great variety of thing else: happiness. Any series of requests for jus-
things we call good. We say that certain actions, peo- tification leads eventually to the response, “Because
ple, and even qualities (such as honesty) are good. I want to be happy!” If someone persists in asking
What makes them all good? What do they have why, there is nothing more to say; happiness is desir-
in common? Similarly, we call things as diverse as able for its own sake.
September 11, Hitler, deception, and cruelty wrong. What is happiness? What is it to live well?
What makes them all wrong? What do they have Aristotle’s answer relies on the idea that human
in common? To answer would be to give the first beings have a function. Just as a good knife cuts well
principle of morality. Why couldn’t there be several and a good teacher teaches well, a good person fulfills
such principles? Because we could raise the question, the function of a human being well. But what is the
What makes them fundamental principles of moral- function of a person? It is what is most distinctive of
ity? What do they all have in common? human beings: to act rationally. A good person acts in
To try to justify moral principles as well as partic- accordance with virtue, and to act virtuously is to act
ular moral judgments is to construct a moral theory. rationally. A good person does the right thing at the
Moral theories are systematic attempts to provide right time, and in the right way, for the right reason.
and justify answers to questions such as What Virtue is thus a mean between extremes. The ability
should I do? and What kind of person should I be? to find that mean Aristotle calls practical wisdom. To
Confucius distinguishes these questions and devel- fear too much is cowardly, but to fear too little is rash.
ops two independent answers to them. The person Courage is fearing what ought to be feared, when it
who does the right thing follows the Way, observing ought to be feared, to the extent that it ought to be
the rules of propriety. The person of superior char- feared, and for the appropriate reason.
acter is sincere, generous, kind, diligent, and serious, How does a person become virtuous? How, in other
doing the right thing for the right reason. Most mod- words, can someone become practically wise? Not by
ern moral theories take the former question as basic. abstract thought, Aristotle says, but by doing virtu-
They focus on action and try to distinguish right ous things. Shakespeare’s Polonius advised, “Assume
from wrong in principled ways. But some theories a virtue if you have it not”; Aristotle agrees. If you
focus instead on the latter question and try to distin- do brave things, for example—initially, by forcing
guish good character traits from bad. Good traits are yourself to do them, by pretending to be brave—you
virtues; bad traits, vices. gradually develop the habit of doing brave things.
Aristotle develops the classic theory of virtue. When the habit is ingrained and automatic, to the
He distinguishes intrinsic goods, which are desired point of being “second nature,” you are brave. In
for their own sake, from instrumental goods, which general, people become good by doing good things.
are desired as means to other things. To justify any There is no rule for becoming good or for distinguish-
answers to the above questions, we must appeal to ing good from bad, right from wrong; a person of
intrinsic goods. Suppose that someone asks why practical wisdom has a highly refined ability to draw
you are reading this book. “Because it’s required for the right distinctions and tell right from wrong.
my ethics course,” you answer. “But why do what’s St. Thomas Aquinas bases his views on ethics and
required?” “I want to get a good grade.” “Why do political philosophy on those of Aristotle. But he adds
you want a good grade?” “I want to have a good many innovations, blending Aristotelian insights into
GPA.” “Why?” “It will help me get a job.” “Why do a Christian worldview. He develops a comprehensive
you want a job?” “I want money.” “Why?” “I want theory of natural law that remains influential today.
things money can buy!” “Why do you want them?” Aquinas begins with Aristotle’s idea that human good
To stop the chain of questions, you must appeal to depends on human nature. To live well—to excel or
something that is intrinsically good. Every time you flourish—is to fulfill one’s function well. Just as an

bon38219_pt1_007-162.indd 8 12/28/11 8:14 PM


First Principles 9

excellent knife cuts well and an excellent eye sees we are tells us what we ought to do and be. The uni-
well, an excellent human being displays excellence verse is ordered so that we naturally tend to pursue
in rational activity. As these examples suggest, dif- good and avoid evil. Our own dispositions thus pro-
ferent things have different functions. In general, the vide a test. We are naturally disposed to pursue good
function of a thing depends on its nature. So, what and avoid evil. We have a natural tendency not only
something ought to do and be depends on its func- to have certain inclinations (toward food, drink, and
tion, which in turn depends on its nature. sex, for example), but also to control them through
Aquinas adds God to this Aristotelian picture. the exercise of reason. If lust is natural, so are ratio-
God establishes the order of nature, determining the nality, shame, and self-restraint.
natures of things and their functions and their excel- Aquinas classifies the precepts of natural law into
lences. God thus indirectly establishes not only the three groups: (1) laws of self-preservation, (2) laws
physical laws that constitute the order of nature but of biological welfare, and (3) laws of reason.
also the natural laws that free beings ought to obey. Aquinas does not develop his theory of natural
Since human nature is distinctively rational, law itself law into a comprehensive political philosophy. Nev-
is essentially a matter of reason. ertheless, several important theses follow from it.
Aquinas distinguishes several different kinds of First, human law aims at the common good. Sec-
law. Eternal law is the law of nature, established by ond, the purpose of human law is to help people
God, that governs the entire universe. Everything in follow natural law—that is, to make them virtuous.
the universe obeys eternal law and does so neces- Law is essentially paternalistic, restricting people’s
sarily. Science investigates eternal law and tries to freedom for their own good. The law accomplishes
describe it. Natural law is normative; it prescribes this by training people to recognize right and wrong.
what things should do and be. Since a thing’s nature Third, human law must be flexible. As Aristotle said,
determines its function and thus its virtue—what it virtue is a mean; there is no strict rule for finding it.
ought to do and be—eternal law determines natural Human laws cannot take into account the full com-
law. Natural law is the manifestation of eternal law plexity of the world; they inevitably oversimplify.
in creatures capable of rational choice and activity. We must create law to regulate our behavior but also
Natural law manifests the eternal law by way of “the must allow for exceptions in those cases in which
light of natural reason.” God imprints on us the natu- the law does not make sense. One might think that
ral ability to tell right from wrong. we may solve this problem by making law more
Aquinas also distinguishes natural law from specific. We might, for example, require people to
human law. Natural law is fully general and uni- return goods held in trust unless such return poses
versal, but human law must apply to particular cir- a risk to national security. But this only makes the
cumstances in specific ways. Natural law relates to problem worse. We are better off with general laws
human law as principles relate to conclusions drawn flexibly applied. Fourth, a law that is unjust or fails
from them. One can think of natural law, then, as to promote the common good, in general or in a
comprising the axioms of the moral law in general. particular case, has no authority as law. It should not
Because natural law serves as an axiom of the moral be obeyed.
law, it must be self-evident; it cannot be a conclu- Finally, just as people have a natural inclination
sion from some other premise. Precepts of natural to virtue, they have a natural inclination to live in
law must be both general and obvious. That might certain social structures: in families, in communities,
make it seem that natural law has little content. Pur- and in states. These social institutions are natural, not
sue good; avoid evil. Everyone can agree to that. But conventional; they thus have moral force. People are
what is good? What is evil? inherently social, as Aristotle observed. More specifi-
Here, Aquinas appeals to human nature. As cally, they are naturally family members, members
Aristotle argued, human excellence depends on our of communities, and citizens. Law, therefore, should
characteristic function, which depends in turn on serve to strengthen these natural institutions.
our nature. This is true in two senses. What we are The Enlightenment produced a great challenge
determines what we ought to do and be. And what to morality in the thought of David Hume. Aristotle

bon38219_pt1_007-162.indd 9 12/28/11 8:14 PM


Another random document with
no related content on Scribd:
The Project Gutenberg eBook of Julia Cary
and her kitten
This ebook is for the use of anyone anywhere in the United States
and most other parts of the world at no cost and with almost no
restrictions whatsoever. You may copy it, give it away or re-use it
under the terms of the Project Gutenberg License included with this
ebook or online at www.gutenberg.org. If you are not located in the
United States, you will have to check the laws of the country where
you are located before using this eBook.

Title: Julia Cary and her kitten

Author: M. E. Miller

Release date: September 17, 2023 [eBook #71668]

Language: English

Original publication: New York: American Tract Society, 1873

Credits: Bob Taylor, Charlene Taylor and the Online Distributed


Proofreading Team at https://www.pgdp.net (This file was
produced from images generously made available by The
Internet Archive/American Libraries.)

*** START OF THE PROJECT GUTENBERG EBOOK JULIA CARY


AND HER KITTEN ***
JULIA CARY
AND
HER KITTEN.

BY MRS. M. E. MILLER.

AMERICAN TRACT SOCIETY,


150 NASSAU STREET, NEW YORK.
Entered, according to Act of Congress, in the year 1873, by the American
Tract Society, in the Office of the Librarian of Congress, at Washington.
JULIA CARY
AND

HER KITTEN.
CHAPTER I.
A SAIL.

A fine large steamboat was sailing up the Hudson river one


summer morning.
Up and down its broad decks and pretty saloons skipped lively
little Julia Cary.
“Don’t ask me to keep still, Ellen; I can’t, I am so happy,” she said.
Ellen was her nurse, who had taken loving care of Julia since she
was a baby.
She kindly went to the side of the boat, whenever it was to land, so
that the little girl might see a stout man ring a big bell, and other men
throw ropes to men on shore. These ran and threw the ropes over
huge posts, and so held the boat fast till people went ashore. Then
other people came on the boat; then the ropes were drawn back,
and the boat started on again.
But Julia liked better still to wander about, holding her father’s
hand. He could answer all her questions about the lovely shores they
sailed between. He told the names of the villages they passed, and
showed her the busy machinery that sent the boat swiftly along, far
away from the hot city.
“Papa,” said Julia, “are you poor?”
“In money, child? No, no; I have more than you and I will spend.”
“And you are good, papa, and are not sick. What did that lady
mean when she said, ‘Poor Julia! poor papa!’”
Mr. Cary walked quickly on, leading Julia by the hand.
Down stairs, where trunks and boxes of all kinds were piled, on
their own poor luggage sat a family of German emigrants.
You would quickly call them poor. Their clothes were coarse. They
were eating black bread, because they could not pay for a good
dinner such as Julia and her father had.
Two little girls and one stout boy laughed and jabbered their queer
talk with their mother and father. The mother held a baby on her
knee—an odd-looking fat baby, with a funny cap on its head.
Mr. Cary sat down on a trunk, at a little distance from them, and
lifting Julia upon his knee, he said,
“My darling will learn that she and I must be, in one way, poor as
long as we live. What has that little trot-foot got that money cannot
buy for my Julia?”
Julia looked at the shiny, apple-cheeked little Dutch girl who came
shyly towards her. She noticed the thin dress, the heavy shoes, the
ugly net over her yellow hair. Surely, Julia bought for herself lovelier
things than those.
Julia kept thinking. The strange child too was thinking, and drew
so near that she was scared at last to find herself so far from her
mother. She turned and ran back. The mother held out her arm,
hugged the little girl close to her heart, and kissed her between her
blue eyes.
That kiss told Julia what her father meant. Laying her head upon
his shoulder, she said, “I know, papa; she has her own dear mother.
But mine—O papa!”
Julia’s tears choked back the words that might have told you her
dear mother was in heaven.
Sitting there, Julia and her father felt how very poor she was in
losing mother-love and care and kisses, like that which blessed
those little strangers. The Germans had no house, no land—had
only money enough to take them West, where they must work hard
all day, early and late. But they had each other.
They might tell us that life and love are God’s best blessings.
Health and wealth are also his rich gifts, but not so dear—oh no! oh
no!
CHAPTER II.
A RIDE.

At Catskill Mr. Cary and Julia left the boat; and Ellen, too, with her
hands full of baskets, bags, and wraps.
They walked aside from the crowd on the dock, towards a man
who was holding the reins of two bright bay horses.
This was uncle Benjamin. He had left his hay-field, ten miles away,
and come down to the river to welcome our travellers. Smiles and
black eyes lit up his sunburnt face cheerily.
If you had been looking off from the boat to see Julia go ashore,
you would have wished you too might have been lifted by his strong
arms into his easy carriage.
Ellen and the baskets were next put in. Mr. Cary sprang to the
front seat, and uncle Benjamin got up beside him.
The horses started as if they were in a hurry to get through the
bars of their green pasture-lot again. Away they went over the hills.
Julia thought there was no other man so good as uncle Benjamin.
She thought he owned all that country, that all the calves and colts
scampering about the farms they passed belonged to him, and many
an eager question she asked about what she saw.
“O uncle Benjamin!” she shouted at last, so quickly that he half
stopped his horses, as he turned to hear, “have you got any kittens
for me?”
“Ha! ha!” he laughed; “I thought you had dropped your hat or bag
in the road. Got any kittens? Can’t say. Charley or Johnny will know.”
A few more hills were crossed, and uncle Benjamin was at home.
Aunt Abby stood smiling at the open door; but the boys met the
carriage at the gate. They were in haste to see this dear little cousin
who came but once a year.
Before Mr. Cary had hung up his dusty linen coat, Julia whispered,
“Papa, they have got kittens, four of them. Please ask if I may
have one for my own self.”
Mr. Cary told aunt Abby how lonely Julia was at home without her
mother; how for weeks her heart had been so sad she could hardly
play at all. She was getting used to the stillness in the house, and
the heartache was wearing away. But she wanted some live thing to
play with, she said, and hoped to take home a real kitten.
“Poor little motherless girl!” sighed aunt Abby.
When called to tea, Julia came in smiling, with Charley and
Johnny, who had been showing her their out-door pets.
After tea, Julia led her father to the old woodhouse stairway, where
there was a more lowly kind of mother-love to be seen.
A large contented-looking cat lay on the door-step, winking
fearlessly at them. The cunningest of four kittens was climbing on
her back. Two prettier kittens were having a frolic at her feet, while
the other one sat soberly looking on. Sometimes the wild ones rolled
over and over each other down the steps.
“Did you ever see such lovely, pesshus kittens, papa dear?”
“None so precious to you and this mother-cat,” her papa said,
smiling to see her so pleased.
“And I can have one! All the folks say so. Now help me find out,
papa, which is the bestest kitty.”
“I wish a mouse would come along; then I’d tell you which I think is
the best,” said Charley.
“But I don’t care ’bout my kitty’s catching mice; I only want her to
play with me. She shall have milk to drink, and part of my dinner
every day.”
“Kittens would look prettier to me if I didn’t know they would grow
to be cats,” Johnny said.

“Bah! yes!” said Charley. “Up on that shed, by your bedroom


window—see, Julia—see that big striped cat! Johnny and I just loved
him when he was a kitten. But he kills our birds, and that we can’t
forgive.”
Up spoke kind-hearted Johnny: “I b’lieve he’s the wickedest,
badest cat that meows. So many nests he has spoiled! Then the
mother-birds cry and call so, we have to stop our ears. When I get a
gun, I b’lieve I’ll shoot you, Mr. Tom.”
Johnny handled a willow-rod as if it were a gun, and pointed it up
at the big gray cat. But it did not fear him, it was up so high. Perhaps
it knew nothing about guns.
“Better go to bed now, Julia. Dream about the kittens, and in the
morning we will see which one we like the best.”
CHAPTER III.
CHOOSING THE KITTEN.

In the morning two little girls, Anne and Rose, from the next
farmhouse, came to ask for a kitten.
Aunt Abby said Julia must first choose her own.
The liveliest kitty had a black-and-white coat, with black cap and
ears. Its clean white face and hands and feet pleased Julia so well,
that she tied her red ribbon around its neck.
Anne and Rose were just as content with the gray ones the boys
gave to them.
When they went away, each carried a kitten in her arms, and each
very sweetly asked Julia to come to see them.
“We will,” said aunt Abby, “to see how the kittens like their new
home.”
“Come here, Papa Cary,” this kind aunt said after breakfast, when
he sat under the cherry-tree reading his newspaper; “come to my
kitchen-door and see a pretty picture.”
Papa went with her, and saw his Julia trying to make the kitten
love her.
She had a basin of new milk, of which kitty had been drinking.
Now it was purring its thanks. Julia laid her fat cheek against its furry
side to hear the purr-purring sound.
“Dear little kitty, you will love me, wont you? My dollies just lie still,
and can’t love a bit. You nice, warm, live kitty, you wont let me be
lonesome any more.”
CHAPTER IV.
LITTLE THIEVES.

So now there were only two kittens in aunt Abby’s house.


Julia found them in mischief that very day, up on the kitchen table.
Aunt Abby was getting ready to make a custard. She had gone to
the pantry for some eggs, and had left the milk on the table, and the
sugar-jar uncovered. When she stepped out of the kitchen, the
kittens stepped in. The flies, perhaps, had been in before.
No little boy or girl would meddle with sugar or milk left in the way;
but it is hard to teach kittens that it is wrong to touch what is not
theirs.

You might also like