Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 9

See discussions, stats, and author profiles for this publication at: https://www.researchgate.

net/publication/281632730

Technology is a laughing matter: Bergson, the comic and technology

Article in AI & SOCIETY · September 2015


DOI: 10.1007/s00146-015-0612-9

CITATIONS READS

3 1,176

1 author:

Steffen Steinert
Delft University of Technology
32 PUBLICATIONS 312 CITATIONS

SEE PROFILE

Some of the authors of this publication are also working on these related projects:

‘Developing socially responsible innovations: The role of values and moral emotions' View project

Design for changing values: a theory of value change in sociotechnical systems View project

All content following this page was uploaded by Steffen Steinert on 12 January 2016.

The user has requested enhancement of the downloaded file.


AI & Soc
DOI 10.1007/s00146-015-0612-9

ORIGINAL ARTICLE

Technology is a laughing matter: Bergson, the comic


and technology
Steffen Steinert1

Received: 2 March 2015 / Accepted: 7 August 2015


 Springer-Verlag London 2015

Abstract There seems to be no connection between have consulted features him and his contribution to phi-
philosophy of humor and the philosophy of technology. In losophy of technology1. The main reason for the absence of
this paper, I want to make the case that there is. I will Bergson in the philosophical literature on technology may
pursue a twofold goal in this paper: First, I will take an be that Bergson never explicitly focused on technology in
account from one of the seminal figures in the philosophy his writings. On the rare occasions that Bergson is men-
of humor, Henri Bergson, and bring out its merits for a tioned, it is usually for his book Creative Evolution (1998)
philosophy of technology. Bergson has never been fully and his anthropological characterization of man as homo
appreciated as a philosopher of technology. I will fill this faber (Mitcham 1994). There are, however, some recent
gap and show that Bergson’s account of the comic contains exceptions that are noteworthy. Ruse (2005) uses Bergson
some interesting insights about our relation to technology. to ground his argument for the importance of a philosophy
Second, I will show that humor and the comic open up a of technology and Marrati (2010) draws attention to
new perspective on technology that may facilitate new Bergson’s thoughts about the relation of technology to
ways of thinking about our technological culture. organisms and how technology extends our organs. My aim
here is to show that Bergson is relevant for a philosophy of
Keywords Bergson  Humor  Philosophy of technology. In order to do so, I will leave aside the works
technology  Philosophy of humor  Laughter  The that have received all the attention so far (Creative Evo-
comic lution and Matter and Memory) and take some ideas from a
small book called On Laughter, a book that deals with
comic amusement and laughter. The second goal is to bring
1 Introduction together the philosophy of technology and the philosophy
of humor. Humor as a response to technology has not
In this paper, I will explore whether Bergson’s account of gotten the attention that it deserves. I will try to show that
comic amusement can be made fruitful for philosophy of humor can provide a fresh and new perspective on our
technology. Associated with this enterprise are two goals: relation to technology.
First, I attempt to fill a gap in the intellectual landscape My focus here is also twofold: First, I will focus
because Henri Bergson is absent from the philosophical exclusively on Bergson’s text On Laughter. I will not
literature on technology. No seminal compendium that I engage with his other writings because it is the account in

1
In Scharff and Dusek (2003) Bergson is mentioned only 5 times. In
& Steffen Steinert the more recent Berg Olsen et al. (2012) Bergson’s name is mentioned
steffen.steinert@campus.lmu.de only once. Bergson is also absent from a lot of introductions to the
philosophy of technology. To name just a few: Ferré (1995) does not
1
Graduate School of Systemic Neurosciences, Research mention him at all and Dusek (2006) mentions him once. And last but
Center Neurophilosophy, Ludwig-Maximilians-Universität not least: The entry on philosophy of technology in the Stanford
München, Schellingstraße 10, Room J 308, 80539 Munich, Encyclopedia of Philosophy does not mention Bergson at all
Germany (Franssen et al. 2013).

123
AI & Soc

this book where interesting connections to a philosophy of inflexible. To get a grasp on mental inflexibility it will be
technology can be found. As for the second focus: The useful to consider an example too: Habits often dictate how
elements of Bergson’s account that I will be considering in we go about things. The way most people start the day can
this paper are only the elements that are of interest for a be reminiscent of a robot on autopilot: Getting up, making
philosophy of technology. That means I will not give a full coffee the same way as ever, taking a shower the same way
description of Bergson’s account in all its detail. as ever, getting dressed the same way as ever, having a cup
Here is what the reader can expect: In the first part of the of coffee in the same way as ever, making breakfast the
paper, I will canvass Bergson’s ideas pertaining to comic same way as ever and so on. The bodily movements are
amusement. Then, I will discuss the implications of his automatic and repetitive without the need to think about
account for philosophy of technology. I will conclude with them. Admittedly, the line between bodily and mental
some ideas about the connection between humor and inflexibility is blurry in this example and speaks to the fact
technology. how hard it is sometimes to disentangle the embodied
mind. A clearer case of mental inflexibility is stubbornness.
Sometimes people who have settled on one idea refuse to
2 Bergson: The comic as mechanical change their mind despite good arguments or evidence to
the contrary. More than often this kind of mental inflexi-
Some words of caution: As I have been emphasizing, the bility results from a lack of imagination or lack of reflec-
focus here is on the account that Bergson gives of comic tion: ‘‘The chief cause of rigidity is the neglect to look
amusement and his idea of the mechanism responsible for around-and more especially within oneself […]. Rigidity,
comic amusement. I do not intend to give a comprehensive automatism absentmindedness and unsociability are all
description of Bergson’s account and will only concentrate inextricably entwined; and all serve as ingredients to the
on the elements that are salient for my enterprise to connect making up of the comic in character’’ (Bergson 1914: 147).
Bergson to philosophy of technology. For example, I will In other words, someone is mentally inflexible if she or he
say nothing of the various comedic devices that Bergson does not pay attention to her or his surroundings and lacks
analyzes in vivid detail. Keep in mind that Bergson did not the abilities to pay reflective attention to her or his own
give a full-fledged theory of humor and that he did not thoughts and attitudes. To stretch the idea a little bit, we
intend to cover all cases of amusement. Rather, he identi- could go one step further and claim that the individual
fied the mechanism that he deemed responsible for much of inflexibility has an analogical counterpart on the social and
our comic amusement. political level. After all, the fixation on one idea or one way
Without further ado, the take-home message of Berg- of life is a characteristic feature of some ideological
son’s account is that comic amusement ensues when movements and social ceremonies sometimes make people
‘‘something mechanical [is] encrusted on the living’’ look like string puppets following a script.
(Bergson 1914: 37). I will now expound this claim. But Bergson’s account of comical amusement is
According to Bergson, the element responsible in a lot of incomplete because he does not address the question why
cases of amusement is when a ‘‘mechanical inelasticity’’ the reaction to something comical or funny is a pleasant
(Bergson 1914: 10) takes the place of organic flexibility. experience2. Doubtless, amusement is an affective mental
The source for a great deal of amusement (and in some state that is pleasant and this pleasantness is a crucial part
cases subsequent laughter) is when a person is acting in a of the explanation of why people seek out amusement. In
repetitive and nonflexible way. Bergson seems to have a the literature on humor, there are several offers on the table
spectrum in mind, where the mechanical is on one side and as to why amusement is pleasant. A classic but outdated
the living and organic on the other. Hence, we get what I answer comes from Freud (Freud 1990) who claimed that
would like to call Bergson’s principle of proportionality: what makes amusement pleasant is the relief of cognitive
‘‘The attitudes, gestures and movements of the human body pressure that was used in subduing socially sanctioned
are laughable in exact proportion as that body reminds us thoughts. Another answer comes from the so-called supe-
of a mere machine’’ (Bergson 1914: 29). riority theory of humor (Gruner 1997). Pleasure, so the idea
A distinction is in order here. The mechanic inelasticity goes here, comes from the feeling of superiority over
can pertain to the bodily as well as to the mental realm. another person, as can be observed in put-down humor or
Bergson’s own example for bodily inflexibility is a man on derisive jokes. Others have argued that the pleasure of
the street that loses control over his body, stumbles and amusement comes from the liberation from the demands of
falls down. Here, so Bergson, we are amused because we reason and speech because humor allows the breaking of
recognize a mechanical inelasticity where adaptability and accepted norms or hierarchies (Knox 1951, 1952). In
organic flexibility should be. The man was not able to
2
adapt to the situation, because his body was stiff and Thanks to the referee for pressing me to address this issue.

123
AI & Soc

humor we are free to engage in world-play, to goof around 2.2 The function of laughter
and to question authorities. Most recently, it has been
argued that the pleasure of amusement comes from dis- For Bergson, laughter is a social corrective. Society, so his
covering a mistake in our belief structure (Hurley et al. idea goes, demands from us attention to the situation we
2011). Least we forget scientific evidence: Neuroscientists are in: ‘‘What life and society require of each is a con-
could show that humorous stimuli engage the mesolimbic stantly alert attention that discerns the outline of the pre-
reward system (Franklin and Adams 2011). The enhanced sent situation, together with a certain elasticity of mind and
activity in the mesolimbic reward system is implicated in body to enable us to adapt ourselves in consequence.’’
the enjoyment of experiences and plays a crucial role in our (Bergson 1914: 18). We have to be able to adapt to a new
motivation to engage in activities that promise to activate situation and when the situation changes. According to
these regions. I don’t think that there is a one and only Bergson, inelasticity is a threat to society, because for a
source of pleasure when it comes to amusement and the society to function we need to retain the ability to adapt to
explanation of why a particular humor token is amusing one another. Rigidity of the character and the mind is
and pleasant will likely involve a mix of different elements. something that is suspicious, because it is detrimental to
At the risk of being a little repetitive myself, I want to being flexible and therefore adaptive. Mechanical rigidity
state once more that Bergson saw mechanical inelasticity threatens the social fabric. If you lack elasticity and are
or rigidity as the fundamental feature of the ridiculous. unyielding in your behavior and way of thinking, then you
Something is ridiculous if it behaves in a rigid and repet- are not able to adapt to changing situations in general and
itive manner where it should be flexible. to other people in particular. Witnessing this inability to
adapt, this inflexibility, so Bergson, triggers laughter.
2.1 Context and philosophy Laughter serves as a corrective social gesture (Kivy 2003)
that is intended to discipline the one who has acted
It might help to understand Bergson’s account of the comic inflexibly: ‘‘Laughter is, above all, a corrective.’’ (Bergson
when it is located within the context of his philosophy3. 1914: 197). With our laughter, we want to alert and also
One of the notions that he is best known for is élan vital. In humiliate the person. We want to bring the person back to
a nutshell, Bergson claims that humans are animated by a the realm of humans4. We want her to act nonmechanically
vital force that works behind evolution and that is also and think in a flexible, more human way. Laughter is
responsible for creativity. The élan vital is a force that ‘‘alerting us to the threat of stasis,’’ as McDonald has put it
drives things forward. This élan vital is also responsible for (McDonald 2012: 39). Laughter occurs upon the realization
our flexibility. However, sometimes we do not behave in that some mechanic repetitive behavior is opposed to the
accordance with this driving force but in a rigid and vital spirit (the élan vital).
repetitive fashion. Noticing that someone is not acting So much for Bergson’s account of the comic as
according to this vital force is what brings about amuse- mechanical and his ideas about laughter. After this rather
ment. Bergson was also deeply opposed to the materialism descriptive part, I will now move on to a more speculative
and the mechanistic thinking of his time, especially as it and interpretative part of the paper.
concerned living beings (Guerlac 2006). In On Laughter,
Bergson seems to draw a distinction between the organic
and the mechanical, but we have to keep in mind that in his 3 Bergson and philosophy of technology
later works (most notably Creative Evolution from 1998),
he does not make an essential distinction between organs In this section I show that Bergson’s thoughts on comic
and machines (Marrati 2010: 11). They differ only in the amusement and the ridiculous are of interest to philosophy
material they are made out of. According to Bergson, both of technology. In fleshing out some ideas, I will also
organs and machines are tools that can serve the same connect Bergson to other accounts and authors in the field
functions. So much for the context in which Bergson’s of philosophy of technology and beyond.
ideas on the comic are situated. I now want to consider We should not overlook the following point: Bergson’s
what Bergson says about the function of laughter because ideas need to be considered in the technological context of
this function will become important later, when I talk about his time. He witnessed the Second Industrial Revolution
technology. and it is fair to assume that his thinking was shaped by this

4
Bergson was not the first to see the corrective potential of laughter.
3
I have kept this section as short as possible. The reader who wants The idea that laughter as a social corrective was anticipated by
to know more about the historical and intellectual context of Francis Hutcheson in his Reflections upon Laughter from 1725, see
Bergson’s work is referred to Milner Davis (2014). Hutcheson (1973).

123
AI & Soc

development. Among the artifacts that he was confronted flexible. Especially communication technology allows us to
with when he published the collection of essays that later do things more quickly. One would expect that this results
became On Laughter in 1900 were clocks, automobiles, the in a decent gain of valuable time. However, it only means
machines in the factories and steam engines. During the that we can use the time that we have gained to do other
Second Industrial Revolution, factories became highly tasks. Finishing a task more quickly only means you can
mechanized and turned labor into a repetitive and mono- start the next task earlier. This leads to the familiar feeling
tonous task. Modern technology was seen by many as of being rushed and not being able to come to rest. Time
threatening to reduce humans to mere machines. The for reflection diminishes. Some people feel trapped in a
classic and familiar cinematic rendition of the way modern hamster wheel, repetitively running while losing sight of
technology changed the way humans worked and lived is themselves and what is important to them, because their
the movie Modern Times that features powerful images of mind is always already with another task that needs to be
Chaplin trapped in the cogs of the machine or the scene done.
where Chaplin is reduced to a part of an automatic feeding Bergson seems to have anticipated this development in
machine. The features of modernity are mirrored in comic that he notices that the dominance of the mechanical in the
representations in film, literature and visual arts. North lifeworld has some far reaching consequences for how
(North 2009) shows that a variety of modern writers and people live their lives. As Milner Davis points out, Bergson
artists saw something comical in the repetitions that mod- feared that ‘‘the mechanical that is dominant in everyday
ern machines demanded from humans. Art, literature and life can construct in human beings a kind of phantom self
philosophy are part of the same cultural–technological so that a person thinks and behaves for practical purposes
context, so they all explored similar issues, themes and in ‘mechanical time’ rather than transcending their cir-
ideas. It does not come as a surprise, therefore, that similar cumstances to experience living, reflective time.’’ (Milner
themes can be identified in Chaplin’s and other movies, the Davis 2014: 79). There is the lurking danger of losing
novel Ulysses and Bergson’s treatment of humor (Hanaway awareness of lived experience. Bergson predicted an effect
2012). Hence, Bergson’s thinking on the topic of humor of the technological development that only later received
should be regarded as a reflection of the changes and full scholarly attention. Technology not only changed how
upheavals of industrialization. One might object here that we work, but it also changed the way we relate to the world
Bergson’s idea of inflexibility and his distinction between and ourselves. Acceleration is a constitutive feature of
the mechanical and the organism were a product of their modernization (Rosa 2003) that leads to alienation from
time and are outdated by now. Of course, Bergson knew time and space and to alienation from oneself and others
nothing of recent inventions like cell phones, computers, (Rosa 2010). Arguably, the most recent phenomenon
iPods, the Internet, and all the other devices that make up related to the acceleration of life that we have brought upon
our technological lifeworld. However, a lot of factories still ourselves with the help of technology is the digital time
feature assembly lines, and there are still a lot of repetitive deficit or what Wajman calls the ‘‘time-pressure paradox’’
tasks around. Just think of call center agent who is required (Wajcman 2015: 61–87). Despite the fact that we have a
to unwind the same verbal procedure for a couple of hours. multitude of devices that undeniably help us get things
We should also keep in mind that there are parts of the done more quickly, and despite the fact that we actually
world where repetitive and monotonous jobs are still very have more free time at our disposal than ever and that
common. Further, simply because an account was inspired working hours did not increase over the last 50 years, a lot
by the techno-social climate of a time, it does not mean that of people still experience a lack of time.
it does not have something important to teach for the Not only can technology bring about a loss of reflection,
generations to come. but modern artifacts also harbor the potential for comic
Humans adapt to new circumstances by rearranging the behavior. We are all familiar with the sight of people
environment with the help of technology (Feibleman 1965: talking on the cell phone or texting while walking down the
554), and technology is an expression of our flexibility and street. I almost bumped into people a couple of times
creativity. Bergson was aware of that because in his because I was texting. Since 2005, the number of pedes-
Creative Evolution he explicitly addressed the human trians that were injured due to cell phone use has doubled
ability to create tools in order to act upon the environment. (Nasar and Troyer 2013). Bumping into other people and
The prevailing stance toward technology still is that it things because your attention is captivated by our little
makes us more flexible, allowing for more possibilities and devices is not really a flexible adaptation to your envi-
freedom. Nobody would deny this. But Bergson’s idea of ronment, is it? It is rather the mechanical encrusted on the
the mechanical encrusted on the living reminds us that we living, in that mechanical inflexibility took over where
should not turn a blind eye on the possible negative effects adaptability should be. The phenomenon is perfectly cap-
and that we should consider how technology makes us less tured by a cartoon by Liam Walsh (Fig. 1).

123
AI & Soc

Fig. 2 Experiencing the moment through your cellphone ( Liam


Francis Walsh, http://liamfranciswalsh.com)

Fig. 1 The attention-diminishing effect of cellphone use ( Liam


Francis Walsh, http://liamfranciswalsh.com)

Someone might be inclined to respond that this is an


instance of bodily inflexibility and that examples of mental
inflexibility are not so easy to come by. Consider this: A lot
of people love the GPS device in their cars that guide them
through unknown terrain with a soothing voice and colorful
arrows. However, these little boxes might actually decrease
the ability to navigate in a city when people are on their
own. We can look at empirical evidence that suggests that
navigation systems can have a negative effect on the per-
ception of the external world, in that people do not rec-
ognize important landmarks and buildings (Göktürk and Fig. 3 The constant allure of the cellphone ( Liam Francis Walsh,
http://liamfranciswalsh.com)
Pakkan 2013). The constant and automatic use of GPS may
also result in a decrease in our critical faculty to assess a
given situation. There are anecdotes where people have Another example is the all-too-familiar scene of the
driven the wrong way into a one-way street, crashed into smartphone user who snaps a picture of every scenery or
lakes or got lost in Death Valley because they slavishly food that she deems worthy of being captured, chronicled
followed the instructions of the little box on the dashboard and shared on a social media platform. Here, technology
(Clark 2011). So we should be aware of the possibility that enables a repetitive and automatic habit. A habit that can
technology may actually inhibit mental flexibility and influence what and how they remember these moments in
adaptability. Technology (or the way we use it, to be pre- an undesirable way. In a series of studies Linda Henkel
cise) might even make us less creative. Empirical evidence found the so-called ,,photo taking impairment effect‘‘:
suggests that even the Internet, often praised to be a People remember fewer objects and fewer details when
wellspring of creativity, may have a negative effect on our they have taken pictures of them (Henkel 2013). Here is
mental capacities and learning abilities. Some have even one more example of how technological advancements can
claimed that the Internet turns us into superficial thinkers turn people into comical figures. In a recent New York
and inhibits our abilities for concentration and contem- Times piece (Feuer 2015), the author describes how online
plation (Carr 2011). dating apps change the way people date. He notes that even

123
AI & Soc

in a crowded bar, a place destined for meeting others, 2008). The inability to consider non-technological solu-
people tend to look at their smartphones and swipe through tions is the analogue to the individual rigidity of a person
the endless stacks of possible mates pumped on the screen stuck in his or her habits and ways of thinking, not flexible
by the app. The dating app and the practice that it enables enough to consider other points of view.
have such a strong pull, that people repetitively turn to their I want to push this idea a little bit further. A whole
cell phones to use the app; on top of the usual text mes- society may be ridiculous and comical in the sense that it
saging that is. Again, the cartoonist Liam Walsh expressed lacks intellectual flexibility, that it is repetitive and
this nicely in two of his cartoons (Figs. 2, 3). thereby predictable. The relation between technology and
Just to be clear, the worry here is not that technology how it can be used to foster predictability and suffocate
turns us into mindless automatons or that creativity is potentially dangerous creativity has long fascinated sci-
completely suffocated. Rather, I want to propose that ence fiction writers. In Brave New World, Aldous Huxley
what we should take away from Bergson’s worry con- gives us a dystopian world where everything goes
cerning inflexibility and the opposition of the mechanical according to plan and everybody has a fixed place in the
and the living is that we need to be sensitive to what caste-system. Everything in this ‘‘world state’’ is pre-
technology does to us. We should be aware of when and dictable and nothing out of the ordinary happens. Even
how the mechanical encrusts on the living. The very the excitement that is offered to numb the population is
means that are supposed to help us adapt and deal with predictable and repetitive. The same motif can be found
situations, the very means that have been created to make in another sci-fi classic. In Fahrenheit 151, Ray Bradbury
our lives easier and more comfortable, have a flip side. describes a society where people slavishly go through the
There is certainly a tension between reaping the benefits same repetitive cycle of work and home entertain-
of our use of technology and the way that technology ment every day. After work they sit in front of their wall-
shapes us in undesirable kinds of ways. This tension sized televisions and watch how more or less the same
mirrors the tension between the mechanical and the stuff is repeated over and over. Surprises and creativity
flexible that is at the heart of Bergson’s account of the are not welcomed, because they threaten the peace of a
comic. If humans are supposed to be flexible, then we society where people are homogeneous in their opinions.
should be on guard for the possibility that technology The society that Huxley presents might be called a bur-
may decrease our ability to flexibly adapt to our envi- lesque (Postman 2006). Through a Bergsonian lens it is a
ronment. Without buying into the whole idea of élan rather comical or ridiculous affair because inflexibility
vital, we can nevertheless be sensitive to the way our use and repetition have taken over.
of technology shapes us and pay attention to the way Another closely related issue is predictability. The
technology affects our bodies and minds. contrast between the mechanical and the flexible in Berg-
I have already given examples of how technology can son also brings to the fore that humans are unpredictable.
impede adaptation in a bodily flexibly way and how it can Humans are not like well-oiled mechanisms that smoothly
foster mental inflexibility. Now, I want to introduce a third and reliably function all the time. Humans are flexible and
way, a way in which technology may bring about some therefore unpredictable in their behavior and thinking. In
rigidity on a grander scale. This rigidity concerns the contrast, someone who is mentally inflexible is not sur-
mindset that we use to approach certain problems or situ- prising and rarely creative. The dystopian stories men-
ations and may therefore be called techno-cultural inflex- tioned above give us a fictional (and to a great deal
ibility. What I have in mind here is that technology is so overestimated) account of what might happen when we use
entrenched in our way of life and so deeply connected to technology to create a procrustean. Not only do we turn
how we think about the world, that we tend to think about ourselves into comical figures but we also rob ourselves of
certain issues in a one-dimensional way. There is a fasci- one of the greatest sources of pleasure in life, namely
nation (sometimes even an obsession) with technological unpredictability. Predictability is inversely proportional to
fixes for political and social problems, neglecting alterna- surprise. Taking away unpredictability would be highly
tive ways to go about them. This one-dimensional thinking unfavorable because we have a desire for surprise and ‘‘we
is dangerous because it can lead to waste of money, want varied and unpredictable intellectual and social lives’’
resources and technological pseudo- or short-term solu- (Morton 2014: 138). Too much predictability and repetition
tions. Some problems like disease prevention can be solved brings about boredom. Unpredictability is what makes
with technological fixes such as vaccinations, whereas humans surprising. We should embrace this unpre-
other problems like increasing the reading ability or cli- dictability as a sign of our freedom and creative potential.
mate change do not lend themselves easily to a straight- So the inflexibility that technology may bring about is not
forward technological solution (Sarewitz and Nelson only detrimental to creativity but also to surprise.

123
AI & Soc

I will now conclude the paper with a short recap and References
some general remarks about the role humor may play in a
philosophy of technology. Berg Olsen JKB, Pedersen SA, Hendricks VF (eds) (2012) A
companion to the philosophy of technology. Wiley, Malden
Bergson H (1914) Laughter: an essay on the meaning of the comic
(trans: Brereton C, Roth well F). Macmillan, New York
4 Concluding suggestions: humor and philosophy Bergson H (1998) Creative evolution (trans: Mitchell A). Dover,
of technology London
Carr NG (2011) The shallows: what the Internet is doing to our brains.
One of the goals of this paper was to acknowledge the Norton, New York
Clark K (2011) The GPS: a fatally misleading travel companion.
philosophical potential of Henri Bergson’s ideas about the http://www.npr.org/2011/07/26/137646147/the-gps-a-fatally-
comic for philosophy of technology. I have outlined misleading-travel-companion [http://perma.cc/TH2G-LAJJ].
Bergson’s account of comic amusement and laughter and Accessed 16 Feb 2015
discussed some of its implications for philosophy of tech- Dusek V (2006) Philosophy of technology: an introduction. Wiley,
Malden
nology. I have shown that Bergson’ account of the comic is Feibleman JK (1965) Artifactualism. Philos Phenomenol Res
relevant for a philosophy of technology, although it 25(4):544–559
admittedly requires some interpretative flexibility on our Ferré F (1995) Philosophy of technology. University of Georgia
part. I will end the paper with some ideas about the con- Press, Athens
Feuer A (2015) Taking a swipe at love (or something), The New York
nection between humor and technology and will give some Times, February 15: MB1
suggestions for further inquiry. Franklin RG, Adams RB (2011) The reward of a good joke: neural
Philosophy of technology has already examined a lot of correlates of viewing dynamic displays of stand-up comedy.
the relations that we can have with technology, how we Cognit Affect Behav Neurosci 11(4):508–515
Franssen M, Lokhorst G-J, van de Poel I (2013) Philosophy of
interact with technology and how technology shapes our technology. In: Zalta E (ed) Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy
society. Humor is a crucial human relation to the world. (Winter 2013 edn), http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2013/
Given that technology is an indispensable part of this entries/technology/ [http://perma.cc/85U8-R62G]. Accessed 16
world, humor may also be a crucial relation to technology Feb 2015
Freud S (1990) Der Witz und seine Beziehung zum Unbewußten.
and we should take this relation serious. So here is my Fischer, Frankfurt a. M
suggestion: We should pay more attention to humor as a Göktürk M, Pakkan A (2013) Effects of in-car navigation systems on
response to our relation to technology. Humor may give us user perception of the spatial environment. Design, user
a fresh new perspective on this relation. I have shown that experience, and usability. User experience in novel technological
environments. Lecture notes in computer science 8014:57–64
according to Bergson, comic amusement alerts us to situ- Gruner CR (1997) The game of humor: a comprehensive theory of
ations of inflexibility, that is situations where the why we laugh. Transaction Publishers, New Brunswick
mechanical is encrusted on the living. I want to propose Guerlac S (2006) Thinking in time: an introduction to Henri Bergson.
that the lesson we should take home from Bergson is that Cornell University Press, Ithaca
Hanaway C (2012) Laughing matter: phenomenological takes on the
we should pay attention to situations that have the potential mind/body problem in ulysses and early cinema. Lit Hist
for fostering inflexibility. Amusement is sort of a marker 21(1):6–23
for these situations. Our use of technology can be ridicu- Henkel LA (2013) Point-and-shoot memories: the influence of taking
lous sometimes and we should take amusement as a photos on memory for a museum tour. Psychol Sci 25:396–402
Hurley RA, Dennett DC, Adams RB (2011) Inside jokes. MIT Press,
response more serious. So whenever we are amused by a Cambridge
situation that features technology, we should apply a Hutcheson F (1973) Reflections upon laughter. In: Kivy P (ed)
healthy suspicious look and inquire about the role of Francis Hutcheson: an inquiry concerning beauty, order, har-
technology in the scenario. Technology may be responsible mony, design. Martinus Nijhoff, The Hague, pp 102–120
Kivy P (2003) Jokes are a laughing matter. J Aesthet Art Crit
for a lack of flexibility and for rigid thinking here, an effect 61(1):5–15
that might have gone unnoticed. So, by deliberately look- Knox I (1951) Towards a philosophy of humor. J Philos
ing for the comic potential in our use of technology, we can 48(18):541–548
exploit the potential of humor to give us some insights into Knox I (1952) The comic, the tragic, and the cynical: some notes on
their ethical dimensions. Ethics 62(3):210–214
our relation to technology. Put differently, we should be Marrati P (2010) The natural cyborg: the stakes of Bergson’s
open to the ridiculous uses we often make of technology. philosophy of evolution. South J Philos 48:3–17
Laughter and amusement might tell us something about the McDonald P (2012) The philosophy of humour. HEB Humanities
way technology shapes us. E-Books, Penrith
Milner Davis J (2014) Bergson’s theory of the comic. In: Attardo S
(ed) Encyclopedia of humor studies. SAGE, Los Angeles,
Acknowledgments I would like to express my gratitude to Hannes pp 77–80
Perk, Arun Tripathi and an anonymous referee for their helpful Mitcham C (1994) Thinking through technology. University of
comments and suggestions. I also want to thank Liam Francis Walsh Chicago Press, Chicago
for allowing me to use his cartoons.

123
AI & Soc

Morton A (2014) Surprise. In: Roeser S, Todd C (eds) Emotion and Rosa H (2010) Alienation and acceleration: towards a critical theory
value. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 137–146 of late-modern temporality. NSU Press, Malmö
Nasar JL, Troyer D (2013) Pedestrian injuries due to mobile phone Ruse MS (2005) Technology and the evolution of the human: from
use in public places. Accid Anal Prev 57:91–95 Bergson to the philosophy of technology. Essays Philos 6(1):27
North M (2009) Machine-age comedy. Oxford University Press, Sarewitz D, Nelson R (2008) Three rules for technological fixes.
Oxford Nature 456(7224):871–872
Postman N (2006) Amusing ourselves to death: public discourse in Scharff RC, Dusek V (eds) (2003) Philosophy of technology: the
the age of show business, 20th anniversary edn. Penguin, New technological condition: an anthology. Blackwell, Malden
York Wajcman J (2015) Pressed for time: the acceleration of life in digital
Rosa H (2003) Social acceleration: ethical and political consequences capitalism. Chicago University Press, Chicago
of a desynchronized high-speed society. Constellations 10:3–33

123

View publication stats

You might also like