The Ethics of Resistance Tyranny of the Absolute Drew M. Dalton download pdf

You might also like

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 40

Download and Read online, DOWNLOAD EBOOK, [PDF EBOOK EPUB ], Ebooks

download, Read Ebook EPUB/KINDE, Download Book Format PDF

The Ethics of Resistance Tyranny of the Absolute


Drew M. Dalton

OR CLICK LINK
https://textbookfull.com/product/the-ethics-of-
resistance-tyranny-of-the-absolute-drew-m-dalton/

Read with Our Free App Audiobook Free Format PFD EBook, Ebooks dowload PDF
with Andible trial, Real book, online, KINDLE , Download[PDF] and Read and Read
Read book Format PDF Ebook, Dowload online, Read book Format PDF Ebook,
[PDF] and Real ONLINE Dowload [PDF] and Real ONLINE
More products digital (pdf, epub, mobi) instant
download maybe you interests ...

The Three Escapes of Hannah Arendt A Tyranny of Truth


First Edition Krimstein

https://textbookfull.com/product/the-three-escapes-of-hannah-
arendt-a-tyranny-of-truth-first-edition-krimstein/

Ocean Outbreak Confronting the Rising Tide of Marine


Disease Drew Harvell

https://textbookfull.com/product/ocean-outbreak-confronting-the-
rising-tide-of-marine-disease-drew-harvell/

After the Absolute The Inner Teachings of Richard Rose


David Gold

https://textbookfull.com/product/after-the-absolute-the-inner-
teachings-of-richard-rose-david-gold/

Antibiotic Resistance in the Environment A Worldwide


Overview Célia M. Manaia

https://textbookfull.com/product/antibiotic-resistance-in-the-
environment-a-worldwide-overview-celia-m-manaia/
Encyclopedia of Global Industries Drew D. Johnson

https://textbookfull.com/product/encyclopedia-of-global-
industries-drew-d-johnson/

Evil Lords: Theories and Representations of Tyranny


from Antiquity to the Renaissance Nikos Panou

https://textbookfull.com/product/evil-lords-theories-and-
representations-of-tyranny-from-antiquity-to-the-renaissance-
nikos-panou/

Europe's Century of Crises Under Dollar Hegemony: A


Dialogue on the Global Tyranny of Unsound Money Brendan
Brown

https://textbookfull.com/product/europes-century-of-crises-under-
dollar-hegemony-a-dialogue-on-the-global-tyranny-of-unsound-
money-brendan-brown/

The Aristotelian ethics : a study of the relationship


between the Eudemian and Nicomachean ethics of
Aristotle Kenny

https://textbookfull.com/product/the-aristotelian-ethics-a-study-
of-the-relationship-between-the-eudemian-and-nicomachean-ethics-
of-aristotle-kenny/

J M Coetzee and the Ethics of Narrative Transgression A


Reconsideration of Metalepsis 1st Edition Alexandra
Effe (Auth.)

https://textbookfull.com/product/j-m-coetzee-and-the-ethics-of-
narrative-transgression-a-reconsideration-of-metalepsis-1st-
edition-alexandra-effe-auth/
The Ethics of Resistance
ALSO AVAILABLE FROM BLOOMSBURY

Being and Event, Alain Badiou


On Resistance, Howard Caygill
Resistance, Revolution and Fascism: Zapatismo and Assemblage
Politics, Anthony Faramelli
Hegel and Resistance, edited by Rebecca Comay and Bart Zantvoort
Errant Affirmations, David J. Kangas
Apocalyptic Political Theology, Thomas Lynch
After Finitude: An Essay on the Necessity of Contingency, Quentin
Meillassoux
For Rudi
The Ethics of Resistance:
Tyranny of the Absolute

DREW M. DALTON
CONTENTS

Acknowledgements

Introduction The failure of ethics in the West


A history of collaboration
Ethics reenvisioned

PART ONE The tyranny of the absolute

1 The trouble with post-Kantian ethics: Alain Badiou and Quentin


Meillassoux on the vicissitudes of ethical absolutes
The ironic antinomies of post-Kantian ethical and political thought
The limits of liberalism
The dogmatic structure of nationalism
Alain Badiou and the “smug nihilism” of post-Kantian ethics
The ethics of fidelity
Quentin Meillassoux on the rise of post-critical fanaticism
Factial speculation and radical contingency
The fragility of Meillassoux’s hope
The trouble with speculative ethics

2 Phenomenology, ethics, and the Other: Rediscovering the


possibility of ethical absolutes with Husserl, Heidegger, and
Levinas
Phenomenology’s problem
Edmund Husserl’s reduction
The radical foundations of the phenomenological revolution
Emmanuel Levinas and the possibility of phenomenological ethics
Martin Heidegger and primal ontology
Levinas and the ethical primacy of the Other
Shame and the Other
Responsibility and ethical subjectivity
Phenomenology and the absolute

3 The problem of the Other: Levinas and Schelling on the


reversibility of ethical demand
The face of the Other as absolute phenomena
The absolute and the infinite
Levinas’s God?
The ethical value of Levinas’s absolute
The ambiguity of the infinite
Schelling and the absolute reality of good and evil
The reversibility of good and evil in the absolute
The Other as absolute ground for good and evil

Interlude Sympathy for the devil: The tyranny of heaven


The evil of acquiescence
Kierkegaard’s apologetics for murder
A report on the banality of evil revisited
The tyranny of heaven

PART TWO The ethics of resistance

4 Don’t give up, don’t give in! Jacques Lacan and the ethics of
psychoanalysis
The radical power of Lacan’s thought
Unconsciousness unsettled
The alterity of the Other
Desire for the Other
The subversion of the subject
The Other/Thing
The ethics of psychoanalysis

5 Carving a space of freedom: Michel Foucault and the ethics of


resistance
Michel Foucault and the exigency of ethical resistance
The uses of genealogy
The modern subject—Governmentality, normalization, and bio-
power
The trouble with modern subjectivity and the ethics of resistance
Ethics as care for the self
Technologies of care
Care for the self in relation to the absolute Other

Conclusion The ethics of resistance: A backward-turning relation


Ethics and the absolute
A backward-turning relation
Politics as first philosophy
The political ends of anarchy
The ethics of ab-archy

Notes
Bibliography
Index
If someone here told me to write a book on morality, it would have
a hundred pages and ninety-nine would be blank. On the last page
I should write: “I recognize only one duty, and that is to love.” And,
as far as everything else is concerned, I say, no. I say no with all
my strength.
ALBERT CAMUS, NOTEBOOKS: 1935–42
ACKNOWLEDGMENTS

For All the Devils:

I would like to begin by taking a moment to thank a number of


people in my life without whom the present volume would not have
been possible. First, I would like to thank my friends, colleagues,
and students at Dominican University who have supported me
emotionally, intellectually, and finan­cially as I have prepared the
various drafts of this book. Specifically I’d like to thank the members
of the Philosophy Department, Tama Weisman, Nkuzi Nnam, and
Kelly Burns; the administration of RCAS; and the university as a
whole, especially then dean of RCAS and now provost of the
university, Jeffrey Carlson. The constant support and encouragement
of the Dominican University community was invaluable as I balanced
my teaching responsibilities with my writing duties.
I’d also like to thank the students and faculty of the Departments
of Philosophy and Political Science at Brock University, my second
intellectual home, who have generously allowed me to try out the
various arguments and theses articulated here over the past few
years through a series of invited seminars and lectures on my
research. Special thanks are due to Athena Colman, Michael Berman,
Rohit Dalvi, Leah Bradshaw, and my dear friend and constant ally
Rajiv Kaushik.
I’m deeply indebted as well to everyone at Bloomsbury for their
guidance, thoughtful suggestions, and hard work, particularly
Frankie Mace, who was the ideal editor for this project and whose
constant good humor made bringing this work to publication a
complete delight. Special thanks are also due to Tom Sparrow and
Dylan Trigg, both of whom read early drafts of this manuscript and
made vitally important recommendations, most significant of which
was suggesting I contact Bloomsbury to begin with. I also owe a
deep debt of gratitude to my dear friend Elizabeth Fansher who took
time while on vacation to read through and edit the first complete
draft of this text.
To my family and friends, Robin, Thea, Pop, Paul Simpson, Andrew
Osborne, and Luke Jenner, I owe more than I could ever do justice
with words. I am especially grateful to the stubborn persistence of
David Banach, with whom and against whom the first seeds of this
work were sown. Finally, I want to acknowledge Rudi Visker, whose
influence permeates both this work and my intellectual life as a
whole. Visker not only taught me what philosophical resistance looks
like in a million little ways, he still inspires me to think more broadly
and deeply and to never give up on or give in to my temptations to
be complicit with and complacent to my own desires, the
expectations of others, or the laws of the universe.
INTRODUCTION
The failure of ethics in the West
A history of collaboration
The history of ethics in the West is a history of collaboration—a
history of assent and affirmation. It is the history of the varied
attempt to identify some idea of an absolute good and to define the
various means by which one may live perfectly in accordance with it.
Virtue belongs, according to this story, to the one who both knows
the absolute and has the courage and constancy to act
appropriately: to submit themselves to it willingly, fully, and
constantly. Whether conceived of as an eternal god, universal
maxim, or maximization of happiness or defined as the product of
divine revelation, rational deduction, or moral calculation, the origin
and apogee of ethical thinking in the West has always figured as a
kind of moral yea-saying to some absolute good—an intellectual and
practical acquiescence to some conceived supreme value. So it is
that the history of ethical philosophy in this tradition takes on the
image of an angelic chorus: the voices of its authors filling the
annals of religious dogma and rational intellection alike with the
echo of a million “amens.” “Let the absolute reign, forever and ever,”
they sing. “Let it be in our minds and in our actions, on earth as it is
in the heavenly realms of thought.”
Evil within this narrative has received the lesser part. Cast as a
form of moral failure by the philosophers of the West, evil has rarely
been granted its own ethical power. Instead, it has been placed in
the subordinate position: defined not as a moral force in its own
right, but as the perversion, rejection, or negation of the moral force
of the absolute. As such, evil has been traditionally portrayed in the
West as the consequence of an inability or unwillingness within a
moral subject to submit to the natural right or sovereign power of
the good, either due to blind ignorance, gross incompetence, or
idiotic refusal. In this tradition, evil has taken on the guise of a
purely negative force: nothing more than a kind of petty and
ultimately futile resistance to, rebellion against, or dissent from the
absolute power of the good. In contrast to the “yea-saying” moralists
then, the agents of evil have been caricatured in the West as a set of
puerile “nay-sayers,” epitomized in the portrayal of the devil in
various Christian mythologies and depicted in the book of Jeremiah
in the Latin Vulgate crying out “Non serviam”—“No, I refuse. I will
not serve nor obey the edicts of the absolute.”1
But what has this history of ethical thought wrought? What
practical benefit has been accomplished by the yea-saying
attendants of the idea of the absolute? The kingdom of heaven on
earth? Immanuel Kant’s perpetual peace? Jeremy Bentham’s
happiness? No, none of these. Instead, a variety of totalitarianisms
set up in the name of some form of absolute justice, purity, power,
or security, at least two global wars waged to end all wars and
secure perpetual peace, the North Atlantic Slave Trade, the
Armenian Genocide, the Shoah, Srebrenica, and countless other
massacres. Was all this demonstrative evil little more than the
product of some “lesser part” within us? Was all this suffering
nothing more than the result of a moral reluctance within our nature,
some unwillingness within us to submit fully or bow appropriately to
the absolute good? Can it be that the abject horror of human history
is simply the result of something missing from our hearts or minds—
some flawed conscience, or perhaps some collective idiocy,
weakness, or innate wickedness which has prevented us from
affirming wholly the absolute good and joining the morally upright
yea-saying philosophers of history? Can it be that the profound
suffering of the other which cries out to us from the pages of human
history is really nothing more than the effect of something negative
within us—some ethical deprivation which operates at the core of
our being? Perhaps.
Perhaps the moralists of the West are right. Maybe we are all
“conceived in wickedness” and “born into sin,” as the Psalmists wrote
and the Evangelists snarl. Perhaps we are in fact structurally limited
by the frailty of our finitude, destined to always fall short of the
absolute: capable only of knowing it dimly and acting halfheartedly
in its name. Or perhaps, more hopefully, we simply have not applied
ourselves fully to the task yet. Maybe if only we were to redouble
our efforts to be good, to know the absolute fully and realize its
order completely, we could finally make a heaven for ourselves here
on earth, as individuals, as a polis, and eventually as a planet. But,
then again, perhaps the moralists of the West are wrong. Perhaps all
the evil we have known is not the result of some “lesser part,” some
moral failure to attain the absolute, but something else entirely.
What if it is the inverse that is true? What if the evils of human
history are not the result of something negative within us, something
which refuses or resists the absolute? What if, in fact, they are the
result of that within us which is most positive: our very pursuit of the
absolute good? What if the root of human suffering does not lie in
something missing from us, but in something present within us?
What if evil emerges from our very conception and pursuit of the
good as an absolute? Could it be that the history of ethical
philosophy in the West has not only been wrong, it has been an
accomplice to, and perhaps even the cause of, evil? The aim of this
book is to explore this possibility and to suggest an alternative to the
dominant narrative maintained by the moral “yea-sayers” of Western
philosophy.

Ethics reenvisioned
My goal is to prove two things. First, I want to show that
determinate evil action is not ultimately the result of a privation of or
derivation from some absolute good within us; but, more often than
not, it is the result of precisely the opposite: namely, the attempt to
realize the good as an absolute, a status which, as I will show,
allows for the justification of virtually any action in its name, no
matter how manifestly terrible. In pursuit of this goal, I will show
that many of the most horrifying atrocities in the political history of
the West are not ultimately the result of some dissent from the
good, however perverse, but much more often the effect of a casual,
well-intended, and even at times well-reasoned assent to some idea
of an absolute good. In this way I hope to prove the old maxim
which marks the perfect as “the enemy of the good” to be more true
than ever before imagined. In fact, as I will show, the concept of
perfection found in the idea of the absolute good is, more often than
not, the ultimate ground of and condition for evil.
The second goal of this book is to redefine ethical reasoning in
light of this claim as a form of resistance to any idea of an absolute
good. It is my aim to reclaim the defiant resistance announced in the
demonic non serviam decried by the moralists of the West as the
only means by which any actual good can be preserved and pursued
in the real world. Such a persistent r esistance, I will argue, is the
only ethical maxim we should strive to emulate in our thought and
action alike.
Note that it is not the aim of this book to deny the existence of
absolutes in toto. Nor is it to argue that we should rid ourselves of
the absolute in order to pursue the good. My aim here is not to kill
the gods of the morally upright philosophers, deny their power, nor
call for their excision from ethical reasoning. To the contrary, I hope
to affirm the power of the absolutes they tout. Indeed, as I will
argue, the idea of the absolute is not only inescapable, it is in fact
necessary in order to found and justify any practical ethics. But, as I
will show, the value such absolutes hold, acting as the foundation for
moral judgment, must be reevaluated. It is the aim of this book to
alter the register in which we speak of the absolute in ethical
philosophy. It is my aim to transmute the value traditionally
attributed to the absolute, from good to evil; and, on the basis of
that revaluation, I aim to establish a new model of ethical reasoning
which defines the good as emergent from determinate resistance to
the lure of the absolute.
To achieve these goals, I must first address and dispel a common
misconception within contemporary philosophical circles: namely,
that the question of the absolute is passé—that, in the words of
Friedrich Nietzsche, “God is dead.” This has been the tacit
assumption of contemporary philosophers for the last two centuries:
that the idea of the absolute is no longer of concern for serious
philosophers. Since Immanuel Kant’s critique of dogmatic
metaphysics, such questions have been assumed to be the exclusive
domain of the ideological or the uneducated. Indeed, the aim of
ethical philosophers since Kant has been to identify and detail
various modes of moral reasoning which do not invoke the absolute
as an actual and universal power. Hence, the birth of ethics as
deontological reasoning, moral calculation, and more recently
deconstructive openness. In order for my aims to be achieved then,
I must first show, in contrast to this assumption, that the idea of the
absolute, as the ground and aim of ethical reasoning, is still very
much alive in the West after Kant. I must show, in other words, that
Nietzsche was wrong: that God, as the idea of the absolute, is in fact
not dead, but is rather still very much alive in contemporary Western
ethical thinking. Moreover, I must show that this “God” lies hidden
precisely where we would least expect to find him, even in those
political and ethical philosophies which have grown from the Kantian
critique and the Nietzschean pronouncement of the death of God as
a universal and actual absolute. Only by first revealing the absolutes
hidden within such projects can we understand how very present
“God” still is with us today, and how this idea in turn functions to
ground very real social and political evils. This is the task of the first
chapter of this book.
There we will examine two contemporary attempts to reframe
ethical thought in the wake of the so-called “death of God.” The aim
of this examination is to show that even among those most
committed to the project of thinking of the good outside the bounds
of the absolute, the absolute still manifests as an end to be affirmed;
and, inasmuch as it does, it gives way to any number of concrete
and practical ethical and political problems. To make this case,
Chapter 1 will examine the ethical works of Alain Badiou and Quentin
Meillassoux, respectively, both of whom forthrightly attempt to
diagnose the problem of the absolute in ethical thinking after Kant
and propose a solution to it. Unfortunately, as we will see in detail
there, the solutions proposed by both thinkers are not without their
own catastrophic problems. The nature of these problems will allow
us to conclude that a new approach to the nature and role of the
absolute within ethical deliberation must be developed if we are to
overcome the horrors of the past. Such a project requires, however,
first acknowledging the necessary function of the absolute as a
ground for ethical deliberation. Moreover, it requires discovering a
universal and actual absolute which does not reassert the kind of
dogmatism thankfully laid to rest by Kant’s critique. Only once this
task is accomplished can our larger goal to reevaluate the value of
the absolute begin.
Chapter 2 responds to this challenge by detailing how a new
nondogmatic account of a simultaneously universal and actual
absolute can be discovered within the phenomenological tradition,
specifically within the account of the Other presented in the work of
Emmanuel Levinas. To examine the nature of this absolute, we will
begin there by tracing the genealogy of the idea of the Other qua
absolute within the history of phenomenology, beginning with the
work of Edmund Husserl, proceeding through the thought of Martin
Heidegger, and arriving finally at the ethical analyses of Emmanuel
Levinas. Then, through a detailed analysis of Levinas’s work, we will
discover how the idea of the Other can serve as a simultaneously
universal and actual absolute ground for ethical thought without
falling into the vicissitudes which arise from the Kantian critique.
This chapter concludes by suggesting that the demands levied by
the Other as detailed by Levinas can function as a new absolute
ground upon which to establish ethical deliberation anew. But, as will
become clear in Chapter 3, this solution to the problem of
contemporary ethics comes at the cost of the long-held belief in the
inherent goodness of the absolute. Indeed, as we will see there, this
solution can only be taken, as I have already suggested, if the value
of the Other qua absolute is radically reevaluated.
To see how this must be the case, Chapter 3 reveals how Levinas’s
account of the Other qua absolute is not a force to be casually
acquiesced to, as is assumed by his most committed readers; but is
in fact a force which should be scrupulously interrogated and
diligently resisted. Chapter 3 argues that despite Levinas’s earnest
attempts to found in the Other an absolute ground for ethical
responsibility to be heeded and obeyed, what he inadvertently, albeit
serendipitously, accomplishes is precisely the opposite: namely, to
define an absolute which functions as the actual ground for
determinate evil. In other words, what Chapter 3 shows is that while
we can use Levinas’s account of the Other as a universal and actual
absolute upon which to establish ethical deliberation anew after
Kant, it is not an absolute which we should deem wholly good nor
strive to obey completely. In order to make this point all the more
clear, Chapter 3 will conclude with a brief survey of the work of
Friedrich Wilhelm Joseph Schelling, who identifies in his analysis of
the power of the absolute what he termed the “reversibility” of good
and evil. So it is in Chapter 3 that the first aim of this book is finally
accomplished: that is, the identification of a present and active
absolute moral force upon which to ground ethical deliberation after
Kant, only no longer as a telos to be attained, but as lure to be
resisted. As we will see there, the absolute ground for ethical
deliberation present in the demands of the Other give rise to the
possibility of the good only inasmuch as they are resisted. If they are
obsequiously obeyed, the demands of the Other function as the
absolute ground and condition for the possibility of evil. This
realization allows us to turn from the first of our goals, to the
second: the articulation of a new conception of ethical delibe ration
qua resistance to the demands of the absolute.
The urgency and exigency of the need to develop an ethics of
resistance against the demands of the absolute Other will be
expounded upon in an interlude separating the first three chapters
and the remaining three. The aim of this interlude is to demonstrate
all the more clearly the necessity of cultivating a new mode of
ethical thinking in relation to the absolute. There the concrete
dangers of this ethical reversibility within the Other qua absolute will
be detailed by reevaluating two particularly poignant moments
within the history of Western philosophy where the idea of the
absolute good faltered rather tellingly. The first of these moments
will be excavated from the work of Søren Kierkegaard, the second
from the thought of Hannah Arendt. In this interlude we will discover
how, contrary to the expressed aims of these thinkers, the
reversibility of the demands of the Other, qua absolute good, is all
the more apparent—how, in other words, the good of the Other,
when absolutized, reverts immediately to evil. To make this danger
all the more clear, this interlude will show how actual manifestations
of evil in human history, from suicide bombings to the Shoah, have
all been grounded upon and justified in the name of some concept
of an absolutized good. In this way, the aim of this interlude is to
show all the more clearly what is at stake in the second half of the
book: the necessity of defining ethical action as a form of resistance
against the absolute demands of the Other. It is to this latter task
that the remaining chapters of the book will be dedicated.
We will begin this task in earnest in Chapter 4 by examining the
psychoanalytic work of Jacques Lacan. There, through an analysis of
Lacan’s account of the genesis of the subject, we will see how
various forms of pathology, and what Lacan unambiguously called
evil, can result from an inappropriate relation to any Other which
bears the status of an absolute. In light of this danger we will
explore what Lacan termed “the ethics of psychoanalysis,” an ethics
which, he argued, can only be pursued by learning to say “no” to the
lure of the absolute Other and by subsequently cultivating a set of
practices which can embolden the subject to hold its own against the
inherent threats posed by the Other.
Chapter 5 will develop Lacan’s idea of the ethical necessity of “no-
saying” by way of the late work of Michel Foucault. There we will not
only find a further articulation of the inescapable dangers inherent to
the perception of the Other as an absolute ethical force; we will also
discover a number of strategies aimed at cultivating an ethics of
resistance within contemporary subjectivity. In this way, we will
discover in Chapter 5 a means of pursuing practically an ethics of
resistance via what Foucault termed the “technologies” associated
with appropriate “care for the self.”
The book will conclude with a final chapter which draws from a
number of classical and contemporary sources in order to help the
reader reimagine how ethical deliberation could be pursued as a
form of ethical resistance to the absolute Other. There, through an
analysis of the role of political philosophy in ethical thinking, we will
gain an even more precise understanding of how to accomplish
practically an ethics of resistance and how such an ethics might be
used to counter the imminent threat of evil present in the
contemporary social and political scene.
It is my profound conviction that for any ethics to be truly worthy
of its name, a project earnestly devoted to the pursuit of the good
and the defiance of evil, it must begin with the recognition that any
number of absolutes announce themselves in the world around us
today. Each of these absolutes are presented with the weight and
power of a demand issued in the name of some Other. Ethical
deliberation must begin by evaluating the demands of these absolute
Others. This requires the counterintuitive recognition that each of
these demands, by virtue of their status as absolute, has the
potential of inadvertently leading to evil when obeyed too faithfully.
For ethical philosophy to proceed it must acknowledge this possibility
and its resulting conclusion: that ethical action may require active
resistance to the demands of every absolute. Unfortunately, this has
not yet been the case within ethical philosophy in the West. For
ethical philosophy to continue to have any relevance in the
contemporary world it must renounce its traditional allegiance to the
absolute without denying the role such absolutes play as the ground
and condition for universal and actualizable ethical judgments. It is
the task of ethical philosophers today to recognize that in order for
the good to be defined, the absolute must be acknowledged as a
force to be resisted. To accomplish this task we must begin by
accepting that every absolute demand glowers with the fearsome
potential of justifying virtually any act, even murder and genocide, in
its name. Only by acknowledging this fact can those committed to
ethical action attempt to articulate the concrete and practical means
necessary to resist such potentially evil injunctions and secure the
good.
The task of the first half of this book is to identify and reevaluate
the absolute ground of ethical deliberation as a force which does not
call for affirmation, for saying “yes, thy will be done,” but which
requires resistance, which requires defiantly shouting “No, non
serviam! I will not be complicit in your agenda.” Having shown how
the demands of the Other arise and operate within lived experience
as an absolute, and how such demands ground and condition the
possibility of evil, the second half of this book aims to detail a set of
practices which may be useful for establishing such an ethics of
resistance. One need not restrict oneself to the set of practices
detailed here, however. To the contrary, it is my hope that this book
will inspire the expression of any number of concrete, particular, and
specific acts of political and ethical resistance, all equally suspicious
of whatever Other invokes its power in the readers’ life to solicit his
or her absolute allegiance. In the words of Chairman Mao “may a
thousand flowers bloom. Let a hundred schools of thought contend”;
and may each of them grow from the recognition that the demands
of every absolute must be resisted.
PART ONE

The tyranny of the absolute


CHAPTER ONE
The trouble with post-Kantian ethics:
Alain Badiou and Quentin Meillassoux on the
vicissitudes of ethical absolutes

The ironic antinomies of post-Kantian ethical


and political thought
One of the fundamental problems confronting contemporary
philosophy, or so the story goes, is the apparent lack of any obvious
universal and simultaneously actual absolute good upon which to
ground ethical and political assent. There is no longer any universally
shared God to whom we can turn for guidance, nor is there any
obviously actualizable noumenal realm of ideas or forms from which
we can deduce determinate action. “God is,” as Friedrich Nietzsche
put it, most definitely “dead.” Such pretensions, it is believed, were
unequivocally laid to rest by Immanuel Kant’s critique of dogmatic
metaphysics. As a result, post-Kantian social and political
philosophers have faced a difficult choice: either give up on ethical
absolutes entirely by embracing some form of ethical relativism or
nihilism which rejects both the universality and the actuality of the
good; or, alternatively, attempt to establish some new non-absolute
ground for ethical acquiescence and judgment. It is in pursuit of the
latter that the history of modern ethical theory emerges.
Such attempts to theorize the good after Kant have, however,
faced their own dilemma. Without access to any obvious universal
and actual absolute, they were forced to ground ethical judgment in
relatively non-absolute positions, either by 1) identifying a
universally assertable but non-actual (i.e., virtual) good upon which
ethical judgment could be founded, one deducible within the
structures of reason alone, for example (like the universal rational
duties touted by deontologists); or alternatively, 2) asserting the
power of some actual but nonuniversal (i.e., local) good which could
function as a ground for ethical judgment, one emergent from the
singularity of one’s own being, for example (like many of the post-
Nietzschean conceptions of virtue ethics). Ethical consequentialists
like Jeremy Bentham and John Stuart Mill, for their part, seem to
have alternated between these two poles—at times, they have
insisted on the actuality of ethical absolutes by sacrificing their
possible universality (as is the case in classical utilitarianism which
considers the actual experience of a singular [read: local] individual’s
pain and pleasure, human or otherwise, but acknowledges that this
experience bears no universal absolute value); at other times,
conversely, they have asserted the possibility of universal values by
sacrificing their actuality (as is the case in eudemonic and aesthetic
consequentialisms which make room in their calculus for the virtual
goods of cultural and political values, but by doing so lose the
possibility of that calculus functioning on any universal level to
adjudicate between competing local values).
To make the nature of this post-Kantian ethical disjunction clearer,
think of the options available as falling along a set of Cartesian
coordinates where the vertical axis divides those values which are
asserted as actual from those values asserted as merely virtual,
while the horizontal axis divides those values which are asserted as
universal from those which are asserted as merely local such that
the resulting options available appear thusly:
Another random document with
no related content on Scribd:
*** END OF THE PROJECT GUTENBERG EBOOK PATTERN FOR
CONQUEST ***

Updated editions will replace the previous one—the old editions will
be renamed.

Creating the works from print editions not protected by U.S.


copyright law means that no one owns a United States copyright in
these works, so the Foundation (and you!) can copy and distribute it
in the United States without permission and without paying copyright
royalties. Special rules, set forth in the General Terms of Use part of
this license, apply to copying and distributing Project Gutenberg™
electronic works to protect the PROJECT GUTENBERG™ concept
and trademark. Project Gutenberg is a registered trademark, and
may not be used if you charge for an eBook, except by following the
terms of the trademark license, including paying royalties for use of
the Project Gutenberg trademark. If you do not charge anything for
copies of this eBook, complying with the trademark license is very
easy. You may use this eBook for nearly any purpose such as
creation of derivative works, reports, performances and research.
Project Gutenberg eBooks may be modified and printed and given
away—you may do practically ANYTHING in the United States with
eBooks not protected by U.S. copyright law. Redistribution is subject
to the trademark license, especially commercial redistribution.

START: FULL LICENSE


THE FULL PROJECT GUTENBERG LICENSE
PLEASE READ THIS BEFORE YOU DISTRIBUTE OR USE THIS WORK

To protect the Project Gutenberg™ mission of promoting the free


distribution of electronic works, by using or distributing this work (or
any other work associated in any way with the phrase “Project
Gutenberg”), you agree to comply with all the terms of the Full
Project Gutenberg™ License available with this file or online at
www.gutenberg.org/license.

Section 1. General Terms of Use and


Redistributing Project Gutenberg™
electronic works
1.A. By reading or using any part of this Project Gutenberg™
electronic work, you indicate that you have read, understand, agree
to and accept all the terms of this license and intellectual property
(trademark/copyright) agreement. If you do not agree to abide by all
the terms of this agreement, you must cease using and return or
destroy all copies of Project Gutenberg™ electronic works in your
possession. If you paid a fee for obtaining a copy of or access to a
Project Gutenberg™ electronic work and you do not agree to be
bound by the terms of this agreement, you may obtain a refund from
the person or entity to whom you paid the fee as set forth in
paragraph 1.E.8.

1.B. “Project Gutenberg” is a registered trademark. It may only be


used on or associated in any way with an electronic work by people
who agree to be bound by the terms of this agreement. There are a
few things that you can do with most Project Gutenberg™ electronic
works even without complying with the full terms of this agreement.
See paragraph 1.C below. There are a lot of things you can do with
Project Gutenberg™ electronic works if you follow the terms of this
agreement and help preserve free future access to Project
Gutenberg™ electronic works. See paragraph 1.E below.
1.C. The Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation (“the
Foundation” or PGLAF), owns a compilation copyright in the
collection of Project Gutenberg™ electronic works. Nearly all the
individual works in the collection are in the public domain in the
United States. If an individual work is unprotected by copyright law in
the United States and you are located in the United States, we do
not claim a right to prevent you from copying, distributing,
performing, displaying or creating derivative works based on the
work as long as all references to Project Gutenberg are removed. Of
course, we hope that you will support the Project Gutenberg™
mission of promoting free access to electronic works by freely
sharing Project Gutenberg™ works in compliance with the terms of
this agreement for keeping the Project Gutenberg™ name
associated with the work. You can easily comply with the terms of
this agreement by keeping this work in the same format with its
attached full Project Gutenberg™ License when you share it without
charge with others.

1.D. The copyright laws of the place where you are located also
govern what you can do with this work. Copyright laws in most
countries are in a constant state of change. If you are outside the
United States, check the laws of your country in addition to the terms
of this agreement before downloading, copying, displaying,
performing, distributing or creating derivative works based on this
work or any other Project Gutenberg™ work. The Foundation makes
no representations concerning the copyright status of any work in
any country other than the United States.

1.E. Unless you have removed all references to Project Gutenberg:

1.E.1. The following sentence, with active links to, or other


immediate access to, the full Project Gutenberg™ License must
appear prominently whenever any copy of a Project Gutenberg™
work (any work on which the phrase “Project Gutenberg” appears, or
with which the phrase “Project Gutenberg” is associated) is
accessed, displayed, performed, viewed, copied or distributed:
This eBook is for the use of anyone anywhere in the United
States and most other parts of the world at no cost and with
almost no restrictions whatsoever. You may copy it, give it away
or re-use it under the terms of the Project Gutenberg License
included with this eBook or online at www.gutenberg.org. If you
are not located in the United States, you will have to check the
laws of the country where you are located before using this
eBook.

1.E.2. If an individual Project Gutenberg™ electronic work is derived


from texts not protected by U.S. copyright law (does not contain a
notice indicating that it is posted with permission of the copyright
holder), the work can be copied and distributed to anyone in the
United States without paying any fees or charges. If you are
redistributing or providing access to a work with the phrase “Project
Gutenberg” associated with or appearing on the work, you must
comply either with the requirements of paragraphs 1.E.1 through
1.E.7 or obtain permission for the use of the work and the Project
Gutenberg™ trademark as set forth in paragraphs 1.E.8 or 1.E.9.

1.E.3. If an individual Project Gutenberg™ electronic work is posted


with the permission of the copyright holder, your use and distribution
must comply with both paragraphs 1.E.1 through 1.E.7 and any
additional terms imposed by the copyright holder. Additional terms
will be linked to the Project Gutenberg™ License for all works posted
with the permission of the copyright holder found at the beginning of
this work.

1.E.4. Do not unlink or detach or remove the full Project


Gutenberg™ License terms from this work, or any files containing a
part of this work or any other work associated with Project
Gutenberg™.

1.E.5. Do not copy, display, perform, distribute or redistribute this


electronic work, or any part of this electronic work, without
prominently displaying the sentence set forth in paragraph 1.E.1 with
active links or immediate access to the full terms of the Project
Gutenberg™ License.
1.E.6. You may convert to and distribute this work in any binary,
compressed, marked up, nonproprietary or proprietary form,
including any word processing or hypertext form. However, if you
provide access to or distribute copies of a Project Gutenberg™ work
in a format other than “Plain Vanilla ASCII” or other format used in
the official version posted on the official Project Gutenberg™ website
(www.gutenberg.org), you must, at no additional cost, fee or expense
to the user, provide a copy, a means of exporting a copy, or a means
of obtaining a copy upon request, of the work in its original “Plain
Vanilla ASCII” or other form. Any alternate format must include the
full Project Gutenberg™ License as specified in paragraph 1.E.1.

1.E.7. Do not charge a fee for access to, viewing, displaying,


performing, copying or distributing any Project Gutenberg™ works
unless you comply with paragraph 1.E.8 or 1.E.9.

1.E.8. You may charge a reasonable fee for copies of or providing


access to or distributing Project Gutenberg™ electronic works
provided that:

• You pay a royalty fee of 20% of the gross profits you derive from
the use of Project Gutenberg™ works calculated using the
method you already use to calculate your applicable taxes. The
fee is owed to the owner of the Project Gutenberg™ trademark,
but he has agreed to donate royalties under this paragraph to
the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation. Royalty
payments must be paid within 60 days following each date on
which you prepare (or are legally required to prepare) your
periodic tax returns. Royalty payments should be clearly marked
as such and sent to the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive
Foundation at the address specified in Section 4, “Information
about donations to the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive
Foundation.”

• You provide a full refund of any money paid by a user who


notifies you in writing (or by e-mail) within 30 days of receipt that
s/he does not agree to the terms of the full Project Gutenberg™
License. You must require such a user to return or destroy all
copies of the works possessed in a physical medium and
discontinue all use of and all access to other copies of Project
Gutenberg™ works.

• You provide, in accordance with paragraph 1.F.3, a full refund of


any money paid for a work or a replacement copy, if a defect in
the electronic work is discovered and reported to you within 90
days of receipt of the work.

• You comply with all other terms of this agreement for free
distribution of Project Gutenberg™ works.

1.E.9. If you wish to charge a fee or distribute a Project Gutenberg™


electronic work or group of works on different terms than are set
forth in this agreement, you must obtain permission in writing from
the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation, the manager of
the Project Gutenberg™ trademark. Contact the Foundation as set
forth in Section 3 below.

1.F.

1.F.1. Project Gutenberg volunteers and employees expend


considerable effort to identify, do copyright research on, transcribe
and proofread works not protected by U.S. copyright law in creating
the Project Gutenberg™ collection. Despite these efforts, Project
Gutenberg™ electronic works, and the medium on which they may
be stored, may contain “Defects,” such as, but not limited to,
incomplete, inaccurate or corrupt data, transcription errors, a
copyright or other intellectual property infringement, a defective or
damaged disk or other medium, a computer virus, or computer
codes that damage or cannot be read by your equipment.

1.F.2. LIMITED WARRANTY, DISCLAIMER OF DAMAGES - Except


for the “Right of Replacement or Refund” described in paragraph
1.F.3, the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation, the owner
of the Project Gutenberg™ trademark, and any other party
distributing a Project Gutenberg™ electronic work under this
agreement, disclaim all liability to you for damages, costs and
expenses, including legal fees. YOU AGREE THAT YOU HAVE NO
REMEDIES FOR NEGLIGENCE, STRICT LIABILITY, BREACH OF
WARRANTY OR BREACH OF CONTRACT EXCEPT THOSE
PROVIDED IN PARAGRAPH 1.F.3. YOU AGREE THAT THE
FOUNDATION, THE TRADEMARK OWNER, AND ANY
DISTRIBUTOR UNDER THIS AGREEMENT WILL NOT BE LIABLE
TO YOU FOR ACTUAL, DIRECT, INDIRECT, CONSEQUENTIAL,
PUNITIVE OR INCIDENTAL DAMAGES EVEN IF YOU GIVE
NOTICE OF THE POSSIBILITY OF SUCH DAMAGE.

1.F.3. LIMITED RIGHT OF REPLACEMENT OR REFUND - If you


discover a defect in this electronic work within 90 days of receiving it,
you can receive a refund of the money (if any) you paid for it by
sending a written explanation to the person you received the work
from. If you received the work on a physical medium, you must
return the medium with your written explanation. The person or entity
that provided you with the defective work may elect to provide a
replacement copy in lieu of a refund. If you received the work
electronically, the person or entity providing it to you may choose to
give you a second opportunity to receive the work electronically in
lieu of a refund. If the second copy is also defective, you may
demand a refund in writing without further opportunities to fix the
problem.

1.F.4. Except for the limited right of replacement or refund set forth in
paragraph 1.F.3, this work is provided to you ‘AS-IS’, WITH NO
OTHER WARRANTIES OF ANY KIND, EXPRESS OR IMPLIED,
INCLUDING BUT NOT LIMITED TO WARRANTIES OF
MERCHANTABILITY OR FITNESS FOR ANY PURPOSE.

1.F.5. Some states do not allow disclaimers of certain implied


warranties or the exclusion or limitation of certain types of damages.
If any disclaimer or limitation set forth in this agreement violates the
law of the state applicable to this agreement, the agreement shall be
interpreted to make the maximum disclaimer or limitation permitted
by the applicable state law. The invalidity or unenforceability of any
provision of this agreement shall not void the remaining provisions.
1.F.6. INDEMNITY - You agree to indemnify and hold the
Foundation, the trademark owner, any agent or employee of the
Foundation, anyone providing copies of Project Gutenberg™
electronic works in accordance with this agreement, and any
volunteers associated with the production, promotion and distribution
of Project Gutenberg™ electronic works, harmless from all liability,
costs and expenses, including legal fees, that arise directly or
indirectly from any of the following which you do or cause to occur:
(a) distribution of this or any Project Gutenberg™ work, (b)
alteration, modification, or additions or deletions to any Project
Gutenberg™ work, and (c) any Defect you cause.

Section 2. Information about the Mission of


Project Gutenberg™
Project Gutenberg™ is synonymous with the free distribution of
electronic works in formats readable by the widest variety of
computers including obsolete, old, middle-aged and new computers.
It exists because of the efforts of hundreds of volunteers and
donations from people in all walks of life.

Volunteers and financial support to provide volunteers with the


assistance they need are critical to reaching Project Gutenberg™’s
goals and ensuring that the Project Gutenberg™ collection will
remain freely available for generations to come. In 2001, the Project
Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation was created to provide a
secure and permanent future for Project Gutenberg™ and future
generations. To learn more about the Project Gutenberg Literary
Archive Foundation and how your efforts and donations can help,
see Sections 3 and 4 and the Foundation information page at
www.gutenberg.org.

Section 3. Information about the Project


Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation
The Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation is a non-profit
501(c)(3) educational corporation organized under the laws of the
state of Mississippi and granted tax exempt status by the Internal
Revenue Service. The Foundation’s EIN or federal tax identification
number is 64-6221541. Contributions to the Project Gutenberg
Literary Archive Foundation are tax deductible to the full extent
permitted by U.S. federal laws and your state’s laws.

The Foundation’s business office is located at 809 North 1500 West,


Salt Lake City, UT 84116, (801) 596-1887. Email contact links and up
to date contact information can be found at the Foundation’s website
and official page at www.gutenberg.org/contact

Section 4. Information about Donations to


the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive
Foundation
Project Gutenberg™ depends upon and cannot survive without
widespread public support and donations to carry out its mission of
increasing the number of public domain and licensed works that can
be freely distributed in machine-readable form accessible by the
widest array of equipment including outdated equipment. Many small
donations ($1 to $5,000) are particularly important to maintaining tax
exempt status with the IRS.

The Foundation is committed to complying with the laws regulating


charities and charitable donations in all 50 states of the United
States. Compliance requirements are not uniform and it takes a
considerable effort, much paperwork and many fees to meet and
keep up with these requirements. We do not solicit donations in
locations where we have not received written confirmation of
compliance. To SEND DONATIONS or determine the status of
compliance for any particular state visit www.gutenberg.org/donate.

While we cannot and do not solicit contributions from states where


we have not met the solicitation requirements, we know of no
prohibition against accepting unsolicited donations from donors in
such states who approach us with offers to donate.

International donations are gratefully accepted, but we cannot make


any statements concerning tax treatment of donations received from
outside the United States. U.S. laws alone swamp our small staff.

Please check the Project Gutenberg web pages for current donation
methods and addresses. Donations are accepted in a number of
other ways including checks, online payments and credit card
donations. To donate, please visit: www.gutenberg.org/donate.

Section 5. General Information About Project


Gutenberg™ electronic works
Professor Michael S. Hart was the originator of the Project
Gutenberg™ concept of a library of electronic works that could be
freely shared with anyone. For forty years, he produced and
distributed Project Gutenberg™ eBooks with only a loose network of
volunteer support.

Project Gutenberg™ eBooks are often created from several printed


editions, all of which are confirmed as not protected by copyright in
the U.S. unless a copyright notice is included. Thus, we do not
necessarily keep eBooks in compliance with any particular paper
edition.

Most people start at our website which has the main PG search
facility: www.gutenberg.org.

This website includes information about Project Gutenberg™,


including how to make donations to the Project Gutenberg Literary
Archive Foundation, how to help produce our new eBooks, and how
to subscribe to our email newsletter to hear about new eBooks.

You might also like