Neuroaesthetics and the Trouble with Beauty

You might also like

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 6

Essay

Neuroaesthetics and the Trouble with Beauty


Bevil R. Conway1,2*, Alexander Rehding3
1 Program in Neuroscience, Wellesley College, Wellesley, Massachusetts, United States of America, 2 Department of Neurobiology, Harvard Medical School, Boston,
Massachusetts, United States of America, 3 Department of Music, Harvard University, Cambridge, Massachusetts, United States of America

The famous nineteenth-century psycho- criticized in light of the prevailing plural- cians have focused their attention on the
physicist Gustav Fechner was also a poet ism of artistic styles. To make matters analysis of artworks. For example, Rama-
and art critic. Armed with the tools of more complicated, there is no consensus chanran [7], Zeki [8], and Kandel [9]
science, Fechner sought to reconcile his on the nature of beauty. Kant’s under- have presented case studies focusing on
various interests. He would doubtless be standing of beauty was predicated on an classical Indian art, American and Euro-
interested by technological developments attitude of ‘‘disinterested contemplation’’ pean modernists, and the Viennese Seces-
in neuroscience that have revealed the [2], whereas Friedrich Nietzsche roundly sionists. Explicitly or implicitly, these
operations of neurons at cellular resolution dismissed this notion and underlined the studies aim to extract rules that would
and have enabled us to peer almost impact of sensual attraction [3]. For the lead to a practical definition of beauty,
unnoticed into each other’s working poet John Keats, beauty equaled truth [4], connecting features of objects and neural
brains. But can these tools advance our while Stendhal, the French novelist, char- activity. Zeki, for instance, argues that the
understanding of aesthetics beyond Fech- acterized beauty as the ‘‘promise of power of Alexander Calder’s sculptures
ner’s insights [1]? The nascent field of happiness’’ [5]. More recently, Elaine derives from the black-and-white moving
neuroaesthetics claims it can. Here we Scarry described beauty as an urge to parts, potent activators of the brain’s
consider what questions this new field is repeat [6]. While each of these theories is motion-processing center.
poised to answer. We underscore the respected, not one is universally accepted. It may be no coincidence that the art
importance of distinguishing between Partly this diversity of opinions is connect- these three authors hold up relates to the
beauty, art, and perception—terms often ed to the different functions that beauty culture in which they were each raised.
conflated by ‘‘aesthetics’’—and identify holds within various philosophical systems, One potential danger in aesthetic projects
adjacent fields of neuroscience such as being sometimes viewed in connection is to universalize one’s subjective convic-
sensation, perception, attention, reward, with epistemology or with ethics. One tions and assume that an experience of
learning, memory, emotions, and decision goal of neuroaesthetics is to get to the beauty is common to all. Projecting from
making, where discoveries will likely be bottom of the problem of artistic beauty. individual subjective experience is decep-
informative. How can this be accomplished? tive, for there is ample evidence that
Experiences of beauty are often deeply notions of beauty vary between cultures
Aesthetics and Neuroscience moving, and their importance to the and are mutable even within a culture—
human condition invites a neuroscientific just think of fast-changing trends in fashion.
Aesthetics has a complex history. The explanation. But while deep emotional Moreover, the equation (art = beauty) rests
term derives from the Greek ‘‘perception’’ reactions are often associated with beauty, on shaky ground. Throughout history,
and was coined by Alexander Baumgarten being moved does not always indicate an artists have created deeply moving art-
in 1750 as the study of sensory knowledge. instance of beauty. Consider hearing work that is emphatically not beautiful;
But following Immanuel Kant’s Critique of about a disaster, celebrating a sports Goya’s Saturn Devouring One of His Sons
Judgment in 1790 [2], aesthetics began victory, or smelling a long-forgotten scent. (Figure 1) provides a famous historical
focusing on the concept of beauty, in These experiences are better described as example. Large swaths of twentieth-
nature and in art. During the nineteenth ‘‘sympathy,’’ ‘‘elation,’’ and ‘‘memory,’’ century art have greatly expanded—or
century, the term became largely synony- rather than experiences of beauty. If entirely disavowed—notions of beauty.
mous with the philosophy of art. These neuroaesthetics is to be concerned specif- Such distinctions may seem picky, but
three connotations—perception, beauty, ically with beauty, it must draw distinc- interdisciplinary work such as neuroaes-
art—point in different directions but are tions between mechanisms for such dispa- thetics relies on shared principles, and
often conflated in neuroaesthetics. rate reactions. Since many experiences of requires heightened attention to concep-
Kant is a preferred philosopher among beauty are related to art, neuroaestheti- tual clarity.
neuroaestheticians, no doubt because of
his towering stature in the history of
Citation: Conway BR, Rehding A (2013) Neuroaesthetics and the Trouble with Beauty. PLoS Biol 11(3):
Western thought. He pursued a universal- e1001504. doi:10.1371/journal.pbio.1001504
ist approach to beauty, an appealing Published March 19, 2013
concept for neuroscientists because it
Copyright: ß 2013 Conway, Rehding. This is an open-access article distributed under the terms of the
suggests a discrete neural basis. But Kant’s Creative Commons Attribution License, which permits unrestricted use, distribution, and reproduction in any
concept of beauty has been severely medium, provided the original author and source are credited.
Funding: This work was supported by the National Science Foundation (Grant 0918064). The NSF had no role
in study design, data collection and analysis, decision to publish, or preparation of the manuscript.
Essays articulate a specific perspective on a topic of
broad interest to scientists. Competing Interests: The authors have declared that no competing interests exist.
* E-mail: bconway@wellesley.edu

PLOS Biology | www.plosbiology.org 1 March 2013 | Volume 11 | Issue 3 | e1001504


Neuroscience has provided a heuristic
outlining how sensory signals are pro-
cessed by the nervous system to yield
behavior [10,11]. Signals from sensory
epithelia such as the retina or basilar
membrane are processed in the cerebral
cortex by a series of areas that compute
descriptions of the world: what or where
objects are. These brain areas send signals
to other brain structures that are respon-
sible for evaluating options against expect-
ed rewards—attaching significance to the
sensory descriptions—and ultimately for
making decisions, guided by learning,
memory, and emotions. Below we argue
that a successful neuroaesthetics will
include the study of each of these stages
of processing as they relate to handling,
encoding, and generating aesthetic expe-
riences, rather than an attempt to derive a
single universal neural underpinning of
what constitutes beauty.

First Steps in Neuroaesthetics:


Sensation, Perception, and Art
One approach commonly included
under the umbrella of neuroaesthetics
involves examining art objects in muse-
ums. Here the complication of establishing
‘‘beauty’’ is obviated by treating artworks
as products of a massive empirical exper-
iment. By analogy with evolutionary
theory, the assumption is that the tiny
number of works that survive the selective
pressures exerted by collectors, cultural
institutions, and fads are enriched for the
strength of their effects on the nervous
system. Using this approach, studies have
uncovered various artistic strategies re-
flecting fundamental operations of the
neural mechanisms for sensation and
perception [7,8,12–14]. For example, de-
pictions of shadows in paintings often do
not correspond to the light sources that
cause them [15]. Such unnoticed devia-
tions from veracity reveal important ad-
aptations of the brain to ecological pres-
sures during evolution and development—
in the case of shadows, the relationship of
objects to light sources is in flux and
therefore not a stable feature. Similarly,
analysis of portraits has been insightful,
showing that the outer contour of a face is
more important for face recognition than
the precise configuration of features [16].
And paintings by Paul Cezanne, Henri
Matisse, and Claude Monet show how
Figure 1. Goya y Lucientes, Francisco de, Saturn devouring one of his sons (1821–1823).
these artists capitalized upon the neural
Mural transferred to canvas. 143.5 cm681.4 cm. Museo del Prado, Madrid.
doi:10.1371/journal.pbio.1001504.g001 mechanisms of color [17]. This line of
research is often described as the neuro-
science of art, rather than neuroaesthetics,
since it does not test for beauty [13]. The
approach may reveal the perceptually

PLOS Biology | www.plosbiology.org 2 March 2013 | Volume 11 | Issue 3 | e1001504


relevant properties of visual stimuli— up.’’ His appreciation of the inherently Nonetheless, a discovery that every
contributing to aesthetics as Baumgarten subjective nature of beauty led him to start person’s experience of beauty (however
defined it—but these properties are nei- with feelings of pleasure and displeasure vaguely defined) correlates with activity
ther necessary nor sufficient features of elicited by art, since these constituted for within a specific brain region would be
beautiful objects. An Alexander Calder him the bottom line beyond which further surprising, since it would seem more likely
sculpture may consist of optimal stimuli analysis was impossible. Contemporary that a complex reaction (beautiful!) would
for the brain’s motion center, but this neuroscience has gone much further. A hinge not on the absolute level of activity
aspect of the work does not make it recent study claims that ‘‘all works that within a single brain center but rather on
beautiful. The art simply provides a appear beautiful to a subject have a single the pattern of activity across many distrib-
fascinating demonstration of the compu- brain-based characteristic, which is that uted brain regions—specifically those re-
tations of the brain’s motion-perception they have as a correlate of experiencing sponsible for perception, reward, decision
circuits, and the genius of the artists for them a change in strength of [fMRI] making, and emotion. Indeed, a broader
discovering them. activity within the mOFC [medial orbito- reading of the literature reveals that the
It is an open question whether an frontal cortex]’’ [24]. Leaving aside meth- mOFC is not uniquely associated with
analysis of artworks, no matter how odological challenges [25,26], is such a experiences of beauty and may be neither
celebrated, will yield universal principles correlation meaningful to understanding necessary nor sufficient for these experi-
of beauty. Compositional principles such aesthetics? ences. The mOFC appears to be part of a
as the golden ratio are intriguing possible Subjectivist studies such as these over- large network of brain regions that sub-
universals, and captured the attention of come the difficulty of defining beauty by serves all value judgments. For example,
Fechner, but despite mathematical appeal, asking the participants to first rate visual elevated activity within the mOFC is
the golden rectangle is not the favorite objects or sounds [24,27]. Brain activity reported in studies of neuroeconomics in
rectangle shape of most people [18]. One of each subject is then assessed to their which subjects are asked to assign value to
possible almost-universal may be the own set of ‘‘beautiful’’ versus ‘‘ugly’’ a selection of choices and are never asked
appeal of certain female facial features stimuli. Four experimental-design chal- to consider the beauty of the choices
(symmetry, high cheekbones, large eyes) lenges surface. First, the options are [11,28–30]. The mOFC has also been
and a 0.7 waist-to-hip ratio [19] or high necessarily restricted, and might not in- implicated in impulse control and self-
body mass index [20]. Explanations for clude a truly beautiful choice—the study regulation [31], in changing decision
these preferences depend on a correlation design tests preferences, not beauty. thresholds that influence whether infor-
between the attributes and reproductive Second, different subjects likely interpret mation should be expressed in an evalu-
fitness. Yet celebrated representations of the instructions in radically different ways. ation [32], in attentional processes that
female beauty across history can deviate Third, the use of different stimulus sets in underlie emotion-congruent judgment
considerably from the 0.7 rule, and ratio different subjects makes it difficult to [33], and in moral decision making [34].
preferences vary across cultures [21,22]. control for differences in low-level stimu- Ascribing responses of the mOFC to
Depictions of reproductive fitness can be lus features, which likely drive different experiences of beauty is premature; many
sexually appealing and contribute to patterns of neural activity. And fourth, experiences depend on these processes
aesthetic appeal, but such depictions are, the experiment requires that a given without being beautiful [27,35–38].
again, neither necessary nor sufficient for object retain a fixed preferred status, If the mOFC plays a critical role in
beauty. Another possible universal con- and one that is not modulated by context, mediating beauty, one might expect that
cerns the intriguing discovery that painters which we know is unlikely. As Fechner strokes of the region would impair expe-
typically center one eye along the hori- showed, mere exposure changes judg- riences of beauty. Strokes of the mOFC
zontal axis of a picture [23], taken to ments of preference in favor of the are rare, but the limited evidence suggests
indicate ‘‘hidden principles…operating in familiar option. Brandishing fMRI does they affect self-related systems such as self-
our aesthetic judgments.’’ But the trend not circumvent these problems. More- evaluation [39,40] and do not impact a
towards eye-centering has declined dra- over, fMRI has cripplingly low spatial and person’s ability to experience beauty.
matically during and after avant-garde temporal resolution, and the relationship Alternatively, strokes in other brain re-
movements such as those led by Picasso between the measured signal and under- gions can, paradoxically, enhance creativ-
[13]. Whether this decline is attributable lying neural activity is indirect. In addi- ity, providing support for the notion that
to the relative decline of beauty as a tion, fMRI experiments often only report the expression of beauty depends on a
driving force in artistic creation or indi- regions that show differential activation broad, distributed network. Frontotempo-
cates a cultural shift in aesthetic prefer- between pairs of conditions (e.g., response ral dementia can produce an acquired
ences is unclear. Using celebrated works as to beautiful greater than response to ugly); obsessiveness that is often linked to
empirical data to understand beauty might such an analysis is misleading in situations enhanced art production, usually of ex-
be a worthwhile gambit, but we doubt that in which all brain regions show significant tremely detailed works [41]. In addition,
conclusions can be extended across peo- but slightly different levels of activity for strokes of the left hemisphere, which often
ples, times, and cultures. The only univer- the different conditions, as is likely the cause aphasia, can produce hyperexpres-
sal feature of beauty besides our capacity case in considerations of beauty. Brain siveness [42].
to experience it appears to be its mutabil- imaging provides a blurry, although
ity, itself perhaps a topic for neuroscience. seductively glossy, view of brain function. What Questions Can
And by finessing a definition of beauty, Neuroaesthetics Answer?
A Beauty Center? these sorts of studies sidestep what is at
the heart of our interest in beauty: the Inspired by the power of polling, in 1994
Fechner was well aware of the pitfalls of connection between physical stimuli, spe- a pair of artists, Komar and Melamid, set
philosophical aesthetics and aimed to cifically those crafted by human hands, out to determine ‘‘USA’s most wanted
reformulate the field ‘‘from the ground and our response. painting.’’ The painting was formulated on

PLOS Biology | www.plosbiology.org 3 March 2013 | Volume 11 | Issue 3 | e1001504


the basis of a thousand people’s responses the dynamic, elusive quality of beauty? To and adaptable behavior on longer time-
to questions of their favorite color, favorite address these questions, the field is thirsty scales. This adaptation may account for
setting, and favorite subjects. The resulting for carefully conducted experiments that our ability to make choices across vastly
painting is absurd, showing that a compo- distinguish responses to beauty from those different scales, for example from a
sition with everything that people find involved in more general value-based restaurant menu in one instance and from
beautiful does not make a beautiful paint- decision tasks such as self-evaluation or houses offered for sale in the next instance
ing. Rational reductionist approaches to selecting a juice for lunch. But any such [48]. It seems entirely reasonable—even
the neural basis for beauty run a similar risk experiments are caught on the same likely—that these neurons are also impli-
of pushing the round block of beauty into stubborn thorn—the lack of a cogent, cated in the thorny task of deciding what is
the square hole of science and may well universally accepted definition of beauty. beautiful. Reformulated in this way, neu-
distill out the very thing one wants to One should not always demand a precise roaesthetics is decoupled from beauty and
understand. There is a popular conception definition to make headway, but it might can exploit advances across a range of
of beauty as a fixed attribute of objects, a turn out that the philosophers’ disagree- empirical neuroscience, from sensory en-
notion that much of current neuroaes- ment is symptomatic: maybe there is no coding to decision making and reward.
thetics depends upon. But there is a universal concept beyond the human There may well be a ‘‘beauty instinct’’
distinction between abstract notions of capacity to experience beauty. Our cau- implemented by dedicated neural machin-
beauty and our experience of it—consider tion about neuroscience’s focus on beauty ery capable of producing a diversity of
a specific example in which you have differs from the skepticism that attended beauty reactions, much as there is lan-
experienced beauty. Beauty is an analog, scientific study of other subjective phe- guage circuitry that can support a multi-
not binary, condition that varies in complex nomena such as illusory contours (or even tude of languages (and other operations).
ways with exposure, context, attention, and consciousness); in the case of illusory A need to experience beauty may be
rest—as do most perceptual responses. In contours, the subjective experience to a universal, but the manifestation of what
trying to crack the subjective beauty nut given physical stimulus is universal. So, constitutes beauty certainly is not. On the
with scientific, objective information, we what is neuroaesthetics supposed to study? one hand, a neuroaesthetics that extrapo-
also run the risk of fueling a normative, Experiences of beauty typically require lates from an analysis of a few great works,
possibly dangerous campaign through attention and are accompanied by feelings or one that generalizes from a single
which science is required to valorize our of pleasure [11,27,44]. In the same way specific instance of beauty, runs the risk
experience. Should we deny someone’s that basic studies at the interface of of missing the mark. On the other, a
experience of beauty if the mOFC is not sensory neuroscience and art have been neuroaesthetics comprising entirely sub-
activated? Obviously not. But the question productive—not in addressing why art jectivist accounts may lose sight of what is
underscores the danger of reverse infer- objects are beautiful but in uncovering specific to encounters with art. Neuroaes-
ence, a technique used in brain-imaging the strategies that artists use to generate thetics has a great deal to offer the
studies which posits that activation of a artwork—basic investigations of the mech- scientific community and general public.
brain region indicates the presence of a anisms of attention, decision making,
Its progress in uncovering a beauty
stimulus [43]. Reverse inference is almost reward, and emotion [11,28,29,45–47]
instinct, if it exists, may be accelerated if
always invalid because single brain struc- could inform neuroaesthetics. The field
the field were to abandon a pursuit of
tures almost never regulate single specific will benefit from developing models relat-
beauty per se and focus instead on
experiences. ing observations from the humanities to
uncovering the relevant mechanisms of
Insofar as beauty is a product of the the careful neuroscience that has uncov-
decision making and reward and the basis
brain, correlations between brain activity ered computations at cellular resolution
for subjective preferences, much as Fech-
and experiences of beauty must exist. At within the value-judging structures of the
ner counseled. This would mark a return
what spatial scale, and within what brain monkey brain. These structures, not
to a pursuit of the mechanisms underlying
regions, do we find these correlations? coincidentally, are analogous to those
sensory knowledge: the original concep-
What functions do the brain regions identified in fMRI studies of beauty in
tion of aesthetics.
implicated serve in other behaviors? What humans. Some neurons within these
signals during development and experi- structures encode the value of the choices
ence are responsible for wiring up these on offer, while others encode the value of Acknowledgments
circuits? And perhaps most critically, how the selected choice. Moreover, the neurons We thank Caroline Jones and David Hilbert for
does the activity of these circuits integrate adapt on different timescales, displaying useful discussions and also thank the Wellesley
across modalities and time to bring about ‘‘menu-invariant’’ firing at short timescales College Neuroscience Program.

References
1. Fechner GT (1872) Vorschule der ästhetik (2 6. Scarry E (2001) On beauty and being just. 11. Grabenhorst F, Rolls ET (2011) Value, pleasure
volumes). Leipzig: Breitkopf und Härtel. Princeton: Princeton University Press. and choice in the ventral prefrontal cortex.
2. Kant I (2001 [1790]) Critique of power of 7. Ramachandran VS, Hirstein W (1999) The Trends Cogn Sci 15: 56–67.
judgment. Guyer P, translator. Cambridge: Cam- science of art: a neurological theory of aesthetic 12. Livingstone MS (2002) Vision and art: the biology
bridge University Press. experience. Journal of Conciousness Studies 6: of seeing. New York: Abrams Press.
3. Nietzsche F (1989 [1887]) On the genealogy of 15–51. 13. Conway BR, Livingstone MS (2007) Perspectives
morals. Kaufmann WA, translator. New York: 8. Zeki S (1999) Inner vision: an exploration of art on science and art. Curr Opin Neurobiol 17:
Vintage Books. and the brain. New York: Oxford University 476–482.
4. Keats J (2010) Ode on a Grecian urn and other Press. 14. Tyler CW (2007) Some principles of spatial
poems. Whitefish (Montana): Kessinger Publish- 9. Kandel ER (2012) The age of insight: the quest to organization in art. Spat Vis 20: 509–530.
ing, LLC. understand the unconscious in art, mind, and 15. Cavanagh P, Chao J, Wang D (2008) Reflections
5. Stendhal [pseud. Beyle M-H] (1950 [1822]) On brain, from Vienna 1900 to the present. New in art. Spat Vis 21: 261–270.
love. Woolf PS, translator. Mount Vernon (New York: Random House. 16. Balas BJ, Sinha P (2007) Portraits and perception:
York): Peter Pauper Press. 10. Chatterjee A (2010) Neuroaesthetics: a coming of configural information in creating and recogniz-
age story. J Cogn Neurosci 23: 53–62. ing face images. Spat Vis 21: 119–135.

PLOS Biology | www.plosbiology.org 4 March 2013 | Volume 11 | Issue 3 | e1001504


17. Conway BR (2012) Color consilience: color value: consolidated concepts and new perspec- 39. Feinberg TE, Venneri A, Simone AM, Fan Y,
through the lens of art practice, history, philos- tives. Ann N Y Acad Sci 1239: 130–137. Northoff G (2009) The neuroanatomy of asoma-
ophy, and neuroscience. Ann N Y Acad Sci 1251: 30. Plassmann H, O’Doherty J, Rangel A (2007) tognosia and somatoparaphrenia. J Neurol Neu-
77–94. Orbitofrontal cortex encodes willingness to pay in rosurg Psychiatry 81: 276–281.
18. Livio M (2003) The Golden Ratio: the story of everyday economic transactions. J Neurosci 27: 40. Beer JS, Lombardo MV, Bhanji JP (2009) Roles
PHI, the world’s most astonishing number. New 9984–9988. of medial prefrontal cortex and orbitofrontal
York: Broadway Books. 31. Mehta PH, Beer J (2009) Neural mechanisms of cortex in self-evaluation. J Cogn Neurosci 22:
19. Singh D (1993) Adaptive significance of female the testosterone-aggression relation: the role of 2108–2119.
physical attractiveness: role of waist-to-hip ratio. orbitofrontal cortex. J Cogn Neurosci 22: 2357– 41. Miller BL, Cummings J, Mishkin F, Boone K,
J Pers Soc Psychol 65: 293–307. 2368. Prince F, et al. (1998) Emergence of artistic talent
20. Tovee MJ, Maisey DS, Emery JL, Cornelissen PL 32. Hughes BL, Beer JS (2012) Medial orbitofrontal in frontotemporal dementia. Neurology 51: 978–
(1999) Visual cues to female physical attractive- cortex is associated with shifting decision thresh- 982.
ness. Proc Biol Sci 266: 211–218. olds in self-serving cognition. Neuroimage 61: 42. Chatterjee A (2004) The neuropsychology of
21. Yu DW, Shepard GH Jr (1998) Is beauty in the 889–898. visual artistic production. Neuropsychologia 42:
eye of the beholder? Nature 396: 321–322. 33. Bhanji JP, Beer JS (2011) Unpacking the neural
1568–1583.
22. Marlowe F, Wetsman A (2001) Preferred waist-to- associations of emotion and judgment in emotion-
43. Poldrack RA (2006) Can cognitive processes be
hip ratio and ecology. Pers Individ Dif 30: 481– congruent judgment. Soc Cogn Affect Neurosci 7:
inferred from neuroimaging data? Trends Cogn
489. 348–356.
Sci 10: 59–63.
23. Tyler CW (1998) Painters centre one eye in 34. Tsukiura T, Cabeza R (2010) Shared brain
portraits. Nature 392: 877. activity for aesthetic and moral judgments: 44. Vartanian O, Goel V (2004) Neuroanatomical
24. Ishizu T, Zeki S (2011) Toward a brain-based implications for the Beauty-is-Good stereotype. correlates of aesthetic preference for paintings.
theory of beauty. PLoS ONE 6: e21852. Soc Cogn Affect Neurosci 6: 138–148. Neuroreport 15: 893–897.
doi:10.1371/journal.pone.0021852 35. Cloutier J, Heatherton TF, Whalen PJ, Kelley 45. Schultz W (2011) Potential vulnerabilities of
25. Vul E, Pashler H (2012) Voodoo and circularity WM (2008) Are attractive people rewarding? Sex neuronal reward, risk, and decision mechanisms
errors. Neuroimage 62: 945–948. differences in the neural substrates of facial to addictive drugs. Neuron 69: 603–617.
26. Kriegeskorte N, Simmons WK, Bellgowan PS, attractiveness. J Cogn Neurosci 20: 941–951. 46. Schultz W, O’Neill M, Tobler PN, Kobayashi S
Baker CI (2009) Circular analysis in systems 36. Lacey S, Hagtvedt H, Patrick VM, Anderson A, (2011) Neuronal signals for reward risk in frontal
neuroscience: the dangers of double dipping. Nat Stilla R, et al. (2010) Art for reward’s sake: visual cortex. Ann N Y Acad Sci 1239: 109–117.
Neurosci 12: 535–540. art recruits the ventral striatum. Neuroimage 55: 47. Shenhav A, Greene JD (2010) Moral judgments
27. Blood AJ, Zatorre RJ (2001) Intensely pleasurable 420–433. recruit domain-general valuation mechanisms to
responses to music correlate with activity in brain 37. O’Doherty J, Winston J, Critchley H, Perrett D, integrate representations of probability and mag-
regions implicated in reward and emotion. Proc Burt DM, et al. (2003) Beauty in a smile: the role nitude. Neuron 67: 667–677.
Natl Acad Sci U S A 98: 11818–11823. of medial orbitofrontal cortex in facial attractive- 48. Padoa-Schioppa C (2009) Range-adapting repre-
28. Kable JW, Glimcher PW (2009) The neurobiol- ness. Neuropsychologia 41: 147–155. sentation of economic value in the orbitofrontal
ogy of decision: consensus and controversy. 38. Tsukiura T, Cabeza R (2010) Remembering cortex. J Neurosci 29: 14004–14014.
Neuron 63: 733–745. beauty: roles of orbitofrontal and hippocampal
29. Padoa-Schioppa C, Cai X (2011) The orbitofron- regions in successful memory encoding of attrac-
tal cortex and the computation of subjective tive faces. Neuroimage 54: 653–660.

PLOS Biology | www.plosbiology.org 5 March 2013 | Volume 11 | Issue 3 | e1001504


Copyright of PLoS Biology is the property of Public Library of Science and its content may not be copied or
emailed to multiple sites or posted to a listserv without the copyright holder's express written permission.
However, users may print, download, or email articles for individual use.

You might also like