Simpler Models of Rational Decision Making

You might also like

Download as ppt, pdf, or txt
Download as ppt, pdf, or txt
You are on page 1of 13

Simpler Models of

Rational Decision
Making

• Rational Choice Theory


requires us to assign
probabilities and numerical
values to all possible outcomes
and choose the action with the
highest expected value.
• We now consider a couple of
models that do not require such
detailed information. We may
think of these as special cases of
the RCT model.
The Case Where No
Probabilities Are
Needed
• In some decisions we know
very well what the outcome of
each option will be. The
dilemma is to determine which
outcome is of highest value.
• This situation is called decision
making with certainty.
• From a formal point of view,
this is a case of RCT where
there is only one outcome for
each action and it has a
probability of one.
An Example of Decision
Making with Certainty
• Many shopping decisions are
this nature.
• Should I buy a 24-pack of cola
in cans for $6 or four 6-packs of
cola in bottles for $3 each?
• The cans option is cheaper, but
I prefer the taste of cola in
bottles and it would be a little
nicer to offer drinks in bottles to
my friends.
• Here the only issue is balancing
money against aesthetics. I
know exactly what I’m getting
with each option.
Tips for Comparing and
Combining Values
• The cola case involved only two
value comparisons, cost and
style. Other cases can be much
more complex. When buying a
house, one may need to
consider the cost, distance from
work, number of bedrooms, size
of yard, quality of the local
schools, whether it has a good
place to set up a studio or
workshop, etc.
Ben Franklin’s Advice
• “[M]y way is to divide a sheet of
papers into two columns, writing over
the one pro, and over the other con.
• I endeavor to estimate their respective
weights; and when I find two, one on
each side that are equal, I strike them
both out.
• If I find a reason pro equal to two
reasons con, I strike out all three.
• And though the weight of reasons
cannot be taken with the precision of
algebraic quantities, yet when each is
thus considered, separately and
comparatively, I think I can judge
better.”
The Case where
Probabilities are Needed
but Missing
• Here we know that there is
more than one possible outcome
to an option but we are totally
uncertain as to how probable
the possible consequences are.
• This is called decision making
with complete uncertainty or
decision making under
ignorance.
• [Note that we are only ignorant
of the probabilities.]
Example of Decision
Making with Missing
Probabilities
• Traveling in Central Europe you go to a
small restaurant which has only two
choices for lunch. With some difficulty
these are described to you as “Borscht”
and “Tagessuppe”.
• You know you dislike borscht (a beet
soup) quite a lot. But you have no idea
what the soup of the day would be like. It
could be much worse than borscht; it could
be much better.
• You have no idea at all how probable each
outcome would be - but you’re hungry and
these are your only options.
Analysis of Soup Case

Choose Nearly
Borscht inedible

Makes
Choose Quite O.K.
you
Taggessuppe nice
wretch
Adding Values

• By assumption, the probability of


detesting the borscht is one and we
have no idea how likely we are to
like the Taggessuppe.
• It is easy to rank order the outcomes:
if we’re lucky, the soup of the day
will be better than borscht; if we’re
not, it will be worse.
• There are two strategies at this point:
we could gamble or play-it-safe.
• Which strategy we use will depend
on our personality - and perhaps on
just how unsatisfactory we find the
borscht option.
Rank Orderings of Soup
Outcomes

Nearly
Choose
Inedible
Borscht
[3rd]

Makes
Quite O.K.
Choose you
Nice
Taggessuppe Wretch
[1st] [2nd]
[4th]
Do We Actually Sneak
in Probabilities?
• Some philosophers doubt that
we ever choose without any
appeal to probabilities.
• If we gambled in the soup case,
we seem to have assumed that
the probability of wretched soup
was not very close to one.
• If we played it safe, we were
tacitly assuming that the
probability of getting a good
soup was not almost one.
Treating the Soup Case
as a Problem of
Maximizing Expected
Value
• Suppose we assign equal
probabilities to the outcomes.
• If we now assign measures to
the values of the outcomes
(instead of just rank ordering
them), we can now calculate the
expected value of the two
options and compare them.
• When we already have
rankings, some people like to
assign zero to the worst, 100 to
the best and then set the in-
between values.
Measures of Value of
Soup Outcomes

Nearly
Choose
Inedible
Borscht
[10]

Makes
Quite O.K.
Choose you
Nice
Taggessuppe Wretch
[100] [60]
[0]

You might also like