Download as pptx, pdf, or txt
Download as pptx, pdf, or txt
You are on page 1of 29

Because learning changes everything.

Chapter 8
Formal Fallacies and
Fallacies of Language

Copyright ©2021 McGraw-Hill Education. All rights reserved. No reproduction or distribution without the prior written consent of McGraw-Hill Education.
Chapter Outline

• Define and recognize the three formal fallacies of affirming the


consequent, denying the antecedent, and the undistributed middle.
• Define and recognize the fallacies of equivocation and amphiboly.
• Define and recognize the fallacies of composition and division.
• Define and recognize the fallacies of confusing explanations with
excuses.
• Define and recognize the fallacies of confusing contraries with
contradictories.
• Define and recognize fallacies related to consistency and
inconsistency.
• Define and recognize four fallacies involved in calculating
probabilities.

© McGraw Hill 2
Three Formal Fallacies

• Affirming the consequent.


• Denying the antecedent.
• Undistributed middle.

© McGraw Hill 3
Affirming the Consequent 1

Clauses "P" and "Q" result in an invalid argument whenever they are
arranged in the following manner:

• If P, then Q.
• Q.
• Therefore, P.

© McGraw Hill 4
Affirming the Consequent 2

"If this dog is pregnant, then it is a female.


"This dog is female."
"Therefore, this dog is pregnant."
• This is an example of an invalid argument.

© McGraw Hill 5
Denying the Antecedent 1

Clauses "P" and "Q" result in an invalid argument whenever they are
arranged in the following manner:

• If P, then Q.
• Not-P.
• Therefore, not-Q.

© McGraw Hill 6
Denying the Antecedent 2

"If Sandy passed the final, then she passed the course."
"Sandy did not pass the final."
"Therefore, Sandy did not pass the course."
• This is an example of an invalid argument.

© McGraw Hill 7
The Undistributed Middle 1

This fallacy occurs when a speaker or writer assumes that two things are
related to a third thing, the "middle," are otherwise related to each other.

Example.
• All cats are mammals.
• All dogs are mammals.
• Therefore, all cats are dogs.

© McGraw Hill 8
The Undistributed Middle 2

Schema 1.
• X has features a, b, c, et cetera.
• Y has features a, b, c, et cetera.
• Therefore, X is Y.

Schema 2.
• All Xs are Ys.
• a (some individual) is a Y.
• Therefore, a is an X.

© McGraw Hill 9
The Undistributed Middle 3

Schema 3.
• X is a Z.
• Y is a Z.
• Therefore, X is a Y.

Schema 4.
• If P is true, then Q is true.
• If R is true, then Q is true.
• Therefore, if P is true, then R is true.

© McGraw Hill 10
The Undistributed Middle 4

Example of schema 4.
• If Bill wins the lottery, then he’ll be happy.
• If Bill buys a new car, then he’ll be happy.
• Therefore, if Bill wins the lottery, then he’ll buy a car.

© McGraw Hill 11
Equivocation

Ambiguous claims can produce a fallacy.

Example.
• "All banks are alongside rivers, and the place where I keep my money
is a bank. Therefore, the place where I keep my money is alongside a
river."
• The word bank is ambiguous and is used in two different senses in the
given example.

© McGraw Hill 12
Amphiboly

The structure of a sentence causes the ambiguity rather than a single


word or phrase.

Example.
• "If you want to take the motor out of the car, I’ll sell it to you cheap."
• The pronoun "it" may refer to the car or to the motor. It is not clear. It would
be a fallacy to conclude one way or the other without more information.

© McGraw Hill 13
Composition

A fallacy that occurs when a feature of the parts of something is


erroneously attributed to the whole.

Example.
• "This building is built from rectangular bricks; therefore, it must be
rectangular."

© McGraw Hill 14
Confusing Fallacies: Composition versus Hasty
Generalization

Composition.
• Jumping from a fact about the individual members of a collection to a
conclusion about the members taken collectively.
• "The senators are all large. Therefore, the senate is large."

Hasty generalization.
• Jumping from a fact about an individual member of a collection to a
conclusion about every individual member of the collection.
• "Senator Brown is overweight. Therefore, all the senators are overweight."

© McGraw Hill 15
Division

A fallacy that occurs when a feature of a thing, taken as a whole, is


erroneously attributed to the parts of a thing.

Example.
• "This building is circular; therefore, it must be made from circular
bricks."

© McGraw Hill 16
Confusing Fallacies: Division versus Accident

Division.
• Jumping from a fact about the members of a collection taken
collectively to a conclusion about the members taken individually.
• "It is a large senate. Therefore, the senators are large."

Accident.
• Jumping from a generalization about every individual member of a
collection to a conclusion about this or that member of the collection.
• "Senators are wealthy. Therefore, Senator Brown is wealthy."

© McGraw Hill 17
Confusing Explanations with Excuses

The fallacy of presuming that when someone explains how or why


something happened, he or she is either excusing or justifying what
happened.

Example.
• "I heard on the History Channel about how the weak German
economy after World War I contributed to the rise of Adolf Hitler.
What’s that about? Why would the History Channel try to excuse the
Germans?"

© McGraw Hill 18
Contraries and Contradictories

Contradictories: A pair of claims that are exact opposites of each other


and cannot have the same truth value.

Contraries: A pair of claims that cannot both be true but can both be
false and are not exact opposites.

Example.
• "Visitor: I understand that all the fish in this pond are carp."
• "Curator: No, quite the opposite, in fact."
• "Visitor: What? No carp?"

© McGraw Hill 19
Inconsistency

An individual is inconsistent if he/she says two things that cannot be true


at the same time.
• The fact that an individual has been inconsistent does not mean that
his/her present belief is false.

Example.
• "It is raining on my window as I write this, and it is not raining on my
window as I write this."

© McGraw Hill 20
Flip-Flopping

Gives no reason for thinking that a person’s current belief is defective.


• An inconsistent position is unacceptable.
• The position of an inconsistent person may depend on its merits.

© McGraw Hill 21
Miscalculating Probabilities

• Incorrectly combining the probability of independent events.


• Gambler’s fallacy.
• Overlooking prior probabilities.
• Faulty inductive conversion.

© McGraw Hill 22
Incorrectly Combining the Probability of Independent
Events 1

Example.
• "Bill’s chances of becoming a professional football player are about 1
in 1,000, and Hal’s chances of becoming a professional hockey player
are about 1 in 5,000. So the chance of both of them becoming
professionals in their respective sports is about 1 in 6,000."
• The conclusion is incorrect.

• The two events, Bill’s becoming a professional football player and Hal’s
becoming a professional hockey player, are independent events.

© McGraw Hill 23
Incorrectly Combining the Probability of Independent
Events 2

Cannot affect the outcome of another independent event.


• To calculate the probability that independent events occur, we multiply
their individual probabilities.
• Referring to the previous example, the probability of both Hal and Bill
becoming professionals is 1/1000 times 1/5000, which is 1/5,000,000.

© McGraw Hill 24
Gambler’s Fallacy

A common and seductive mistake that happens when we do not realize


that independent events really are independent.
• Independent events do not affect each other’s outcome.

Example.
• "The last three coin flips have all been heads, so the next flip is more
likely to come up tails."

© McGraw Hill 25
Overlooking Prior Probabilities 1

A fallacy that occurs when someone fails to take the underlying


probabilities of an event into account.

Example.
• "Bill is the best football player in our high school, and Hal is the best
hockey player in our high school. So it appears that Bill’s chances of
becoming a professional football player and Hal’s chances of
becoming a professional football player are equally good."

© McGraw Hill 26
Overlooking Prior Probabilities 2

Prior probability: True or actual proportion of something.


• The prior probability of a fair coin coming up heads when it is flipped is
one in two, or half.
• The prior probability of an unfair coin coming up heads when it is flipped is
a proportion different from half.

© McGraw Hill 27
Faulty Inductive Conversion

Information about the percentage of A’s that are B’s does not by in itself
tell anything about the percentage of B’s that are A’s.
• This fallacy occurs when probabilities are calculated.

Example.
Sixty-six percent of the people who flunked the midterm ate carrots prior
to the test. Therefore, avoid carrots before taking a test.
• Proportion of carrot-eaters who did not flunk the midterm exam should
be considered as well.
• Eating carrots might be a "false alarm."

© McGraw Hill 28
End of Main Content

Because learning changes everything. ®

www.mheducation.com

Copyright ©2021 McGraw-Hill Education. All rights reserved. No reproduction or distribution without the prior written consent of McGraw-Hill Education.

You might also like